The Intellectual Foundations of Political Economy
Karl Marx & Friedrich Engels
Manifesto of the Communist Party
Karl Marx and Frederick Engels
1848
Bourgeois and Proletarians | Proletarians and Communists | Socialist and Communist
Literature | Position of the Communists in relation to the various existing opposition
parties | Preface to 1872 German edition | Preface to 1882 Russian edition | Preface
to 1883 German edition | Preface to 1888 English edition | Preface to 1890 German
edition | Notes on the Manifesto and translations of it
A spectre is haunting Europe -- the spectre of communism. All the powers of old Europe
have entered into a holy alliance to exorcise this spectre: Pope and Tsar, Metternich
and Guizot, French Radicals and German police-spies.
Where is the party in opposition that has not been decried as communistic by its
opponents in power? Where is the opposition that has not hurled back the branding
reproach of communism, against the more advanced opposition parties, as well as against
its reactionary adversaries?
Two things result from this fact:
I. Communism is already acknowledged by all European powers to be itself a power.
II. It is high time that Communists should openly, in the face of the whole world,
publish their views, their aims, their tendencies, and meet this nursery tale of the
spectre of communism with a manifesto of the party itself.
To this end, Communists of various nationalities have assembled in London and sketched
the following manifesto, to be published in the English, French, German, Italian,
Flemish and Danish languages.
I -- Bourgeois And Proletarians [1]
The history of all hitherto existing society [2] is the history of class struggles.
Freeman and slave, patrician and plebian, lord and serf, guild-master [3] and journeyman,
in a word, oppressor and oppressed, stood in constant opposition to one another, carried
on an uninterrupted, now hidden, now open fight, a fight that each time ended, either
in a revolutionary reconstitution of society at large, or in the common ruin of the
contending classes.
In the earlier epochs of history, we find almost everywhere a complicated arrangement
of society into various orders, a manifold gradation of social rank. In ancient Rome
we have patricians, knights, plebians, slaves; in the Middle Ages, feudal lords, vassals,
guild-masters, journeymen, apprentices, serfs; in almost all of these classes, again,
subordinate gradations.
The modern bourgeois society that has sprouted from the ruins of feudal society has
not done away with class antagonisms. It has but established new classes, new conditions
of oppression, new forms of struggle in place of the old ones.
Our epoch, the epoch of the bourgeoisie, possesses, however, this distinct feature:
it has simplified class antagonisms. Society as a whole is more and more splitting
up into two great hostile camps, into two great classes directly facing each other
-- bourgeoisie and proletariat.
From the serfs of the Middle Ages sprang the chartered burghers of the earliest towns.
From these burgesses the first elements of the bourgeoisie were developed.
The discovery of America, the rounding of the Cape, opened up fresh ground for the
rising bourgeoisie. The East-Indian and Chinese markets, the colonisation of America,
trade with the colonies, the increase in the means of exchange and in commodities
generally, gave to commerce, to navigation, to industry, an impulse never before known,
and thereby, to the revolutionary element in the tottering feudal society, a rapid
development.
The feudal system of industry, in which industrial production was monopolized by
closed guilds, now no longer suffices for the growing wants of the new markets. The
manufacturing system took its place. The guild-masters were pushed aside by the manufacturing
middle class; division of labor between the different corporate guilds vanished in
the face of division of labor in each single workshop.
Meantime, the markets kept ever growing, the demand ever rising. Even manufacturers
no longer sufficed. Thereupon, steam and machinery revolutionized industrial production.
The place of manufacture was taken by the giant, MODERN INDUSTRY; the place of the
industrial middle class by industrial millionaires, the leaders of the whole industrial
armies, the modern bourgeois.
Modern industry has established the world market, for which the discovery of America
paved the way. This market has given an immense development to commerce, to navigation,
to communication by land. This development has, in turn, reacted on the extension
of industry; and in proportion as industry, commerce, navigation, railways extended,
in the same proportion the bourgeoisie developed, increased its capital, and pushed
into the background every class handed down from the Middle Ages.
We see, therefore, how the modern bourgeoisie is itself the product of a long course
of development, of a series of revolutions in the modes of production and of exchange.
Each step in the development of the bourgeoisie was accompanied by a corresponding
political advance in that class. An oppressed class under the sway of the feudal nobility,
an armed and self-governing association of medieval commune [4]: here independent
urban republic (as in Italy and Germany); there taxable "third estate" of the monarchy
(as in France); afterward, in the period of manufacturing proper, serving either the
semi-feudal or the absolute monarchy as a counterpoise against the nobility, and,
in fact, cornerstone of the great monarchies in general -- the bourgeoisie has at
last, since the establishment of Modern Industry and of the world market, conquered
for itself, in the modern representative state, exclusive political sway. The executive
of the modern state is but a committee for managing the common affairs of the whole
bourgeoisie.
The bourgeoisie, historically, has played a most revolutionary part.
The bourgeoisie, wherever it has got the upper hand, has put an end to all feudal,
patriarchal, idyllic relations. It has pitilessly torn asunder the motley feudal ties
that bound man to his "natural superiors", and has left no other nexus between people
than naked self-interest, than callous "cash payment". It has drowned out the most
heavenly ecstacies of religious fervor, of chivalrous enthusiasm, of philistine sentimentalism,
in the icy water of egotistical calculation. It has resolved personal worth into exchange
value, and in place of the numberless indefeasible chartered freedoms, has set up
that single, unconscionable freedom -- Free Trade. In one word, for exploitation,
veiled by religious and political illusions, it has substituted naked, shameless,
direct, brutal exploitation.
The bourgeoisie has stripped of its halo every occupation hitherto honored and looked
up to with reverent awe. It has converted the physician, the lawyer, the priest, the
poet, the man of science, into its paid wage laborers.
The bourgeoisie has torn away from the family its sentimental veil, and has reduced
the family relation into a mere money relation.
The bourgeoisie has disclosed how it came to pass that the brutal display of vigor
in the Middle Ages, which reactionaries so much admire, found its fitting complement
in the most slothful indolence. It has been the first to show what man's activity
can bring about. It has accomplished wonders far surpassing Egyptian pyramids, Roman
aqueducts, and Gothic cathedrals; it has conducted expeditions that put in the shade
all former exoduses of nations and crusades.
The bourgeoisie cannot exist without constantly revolutionizing the instruments of
production, and thereby the relations of production, and with them the whole relations
of society. Conservation of the old modes of production in unaltered form, was, on
the contrary, the first condition of existence for all earlier industrial classes.
Constant revolutionizing of production, uninterrupted disturbance of all social conditions,
everlasting uncertainty and agitation distinguish the bourgeois epoch from all earlier
ones. All fixed, fast frozen relations, with their train of ancient and venerable
prejudices and opinions, are swept away, all new-formed ones become antiquated before
they can ossify. All that is solid melts into air, all that is holy is profaned, and
man is at last compelled to face with sober senses his real condition of life and
his relations with his kind.
The need of a constantly expanding market for its products chases the bourgeoisie
over the entire surface of the globe. It must nestle everywhere, settle everywhere,
establish connections everywhere.
The bourgeoisie has, through its exploitation of the world market, given a cosmopolitan
character to production and consumption in every country. To the great chagrin of
reactionaries, it has drawn from under the feet of industry the national ground on
which it stood. All old-established national industries have been destroyed or are
daily being destroyed. They are dislodged by new industries, whose introduction becomes
a life and death question for all civilized nations, by industries that no longer
work up indigenous raw material, but raw material drawn from the remotest zones; industries
whose products are consumed, not only at home, but in every quarter of the globe.
In place of the old wants, satisfied by the production of the country, we find new
wants, requiring for their satisfaction the products of distant lands and climes.
In place of the old local and national seclusion and self-sufficiency, we have intercourse
in every direction, universal inter-dependence of nations. And as in material, so
also in intellectual production. The intellectual creations of individual nations
become common property. National one-sidedness and narrow-mindedness become more and
more impossible, and from the numerous national and local literatures, there arises
a world literature.
The bourgeoisie, by the rapid improvement of all instruments of production, by the
immensely facilitated means of communication, draws all, even the most barbarian,
nations into civilization. The cheap prices of commodities are the heavy artillery
with which it forces the barbarians' intensely obstinate hatred of foreigners to capitulate.
It compels all nations, on pain of extinction, to adopt the bourgeois mode of production;
it compels them to introduce what it calls civilization into their midst, i.e., to
become bourgeois themselves. In one word, it creates a world after its own image.
The bourgeoisie has subjected the country to the rule of the towns. It has created
enormous cities, has greatly increased the urban population as compared with the rural,
and has thus rescued a considerable part of the population from the idiocy of rural
life. Just as it has made the country dependent on the towns, so it has made barbarian
and semi-barbarian countries dependent on the civilized ones, nations of peasants
on nations of bourgeois, the East on the West.
The bourgeoisie keeps more and more doing away with the scattered state of the population,
of the means of production, and of property. It has agglomerated population, centralized
the means of production, and has concentrated property in a few hands. The necessary
consequence of this was political centralization. Independent, or but loosely connected
provinces, with separate interests, laws, governments, and systems of taxation, became
lumped together into one nation, with one government, one code of laws, one national
class interest, one frontier, and one customs tariff.
The bourgeoisie, during its rule of scarce one hundred years, has created more massive
and more colossal productive forces than have all preceding generations together.
Subjection of nature's forces to man, machinery, application of chemistry to industry
and agriculture, steam navigation, railways, electric telegraphs, clearing of whole
continents for cultivation, canalization or rivers, whole populations conjured out
of the ground -- what earlier century had even a presentiment that such productive
forces slumbered in the lap of social labor?
We see then: the means of production and of exchange, on whose foundation the bourgeoisie
built itself up, were generated in feudal society. At a certain stage in the development
of these means of production and of exchange, the conditions under which feudal society
produced and exchanged, the feudal organization of agriculture and manufacturing industry,
in one word, the feudal relations of property became no longer compatible with the
already developed productive forces; they became so many fetters. They had to be burst
asunder; they were burst asunder.
Into their place stepped free competition, accompanied by a social and political
constitution adapted in it, and the economic and political sway of the bourgeois class.
A similar movement is going on before our own eyes. Modern bourgeois society, with
its relations of production, of exchange and of property, a society that has conjured
up such gigantic means of production and of exchange, is like the sorcerer who is
no longer able to control the powers of the nether world whom he has called up by
his spells. For many a decade past, the history of industry and commerce is but the
history of the revolt of modern productive forces against modern conditions of production,
against the property relations that are the conditions for the existence of the bourgeois
and of its rule. It is enough to mention the commercial crises that, by their periodical
return, put the existence of the entire bourgeois society on its trial, each time
more threateningly. In these crises, a great part not only of the existing products,
but also of the previously created productive forces, are periodically destroyed.
In these crises, there breaks out an epidemic that, in all earlier epochs, would have
seemed an absurdity -- the epidemic of over-production. Society suddenly finds itself
put back into a state of momentary barbarism; it appears as if a famine, a universal
war of devastation, had cut off the supply of every means of subsistence; industry
and commerce seem to be destroyed. And why? Because there is too much civilization,
too much means of subsistence, too much industry, too much commerce. The productive
forces at the disposal of society no longer tend to further the development of the
conditions of bourgeois property; on the contrary, they have become too powerful for
these conditions, by which they are fettered, and so soon as they overcome these fetters,
they bring disorder into the whole of bourgeois society, endanger the existence of
bourgeois property. The conditions of bourgeois society are too narrow to comprise
the wealth created by them. And how does the bourgeoisie get over these crises? One
the one hand, by enforced destruction of a mass of productive forces; on the other,
by the conquest of new markets, and by the more thorough exploitation of the old ones.
That is to say, by paving the way for more extensive and more destructive crises,
and by diminishing the means whereby crises are prevented.
The weapons with which the bourgeoisie felled feudalism to the ground are now turned
against the bourgeoisie itself.
But not only has the bourgeoisie forged the weapons that bring death to itself; it
has also called into existence the men who are to wield those weapons -- the modern
working class -- the proletarians.
In proportion as the bourgeoisie, i.e., capital, is developed, in the same proportion
is the proletariat, the modern working class, developed -- a class of laborers, who
live only so long as they find work, and who find work only so long as their labor
increases capital. These laborers, who must sell themselves piecemeal, are a commodity,
like every other article of commerce, and are consequently exposed to all the vicissitudes
of competition, to all the fluctuations of the market.
Owing to the extensive use of machinery, and to the division of labor, the work of
the proletarians has lost all individual character, and, consequently, all charm for
the workman. He becomes an appendage of the machine, and it is only the most simple,
most monotonous, and most easily acquired knack, that is required of him. Hence, the
cost of production of a workman is restricted, almost entirely, to the means of subsistence
that he requires for maintenance, and for the propagation of his race. But the price
of a commodity, and therefore also of labor, is equal to its cost of production. In
proportion, therefore, as the repulsiveness of the work increases, the wage decreases.
What is more, in proportion as the use of machinery and division of labor increases,
in the same proportion the burden of toil also increases, whether by prolongation
of the working hours, by the increase of the work exacted in a given time, or by increased
speed of machinery, etc.
Modern Industry has converted the little workshop of the patriarchal master into
the great factory of the industrial capitalist. Masses of laborers, crowded into the
factory, are organized like soldiers. As privates of the industrial army, they are
placed under the command of a perfect hierarchy of officers and sergeants. Not only
are they slaves of the bourgeois class, and of the bourgeois state; they are daily
and hourly enslaved by the machine, by the overlooker, and, above all, in the individual
bourgeois manufacturer himself. The more openly this despotism proclaims gain to be
its end and aim, the more petty, the more hateful and the more embittering it is.
The less the skill and exertion of strength implied in manual labor, in other words,
the more modern industry becomes developed, the more is the labor of men superseded
by that of women. Differences of age and sex have no longer any distinctive social
validity for the working class. All are instruments of labor, more or less expensive
to use, according to their age and sex.
No sooner is the exploitation of the laborer by the manufacturer, so far at an end,
that he receives his wages in cash, than he is set upon by the other portion of the
bourgeoisie, the landlord, the shopkeeper, the pawnbroker, etc.
The lower strata of the middle class -- the small tradespeople, shopkeepers, and
retired tradesmen generally, the handicraftsmen and peasants -- all these sink gradually
into the proletariat, partly because their diminutive capital does not suffice for
the scale on which Modern Industry is carried on, and is swamped in the competition
with the large capitalists, partly because their specialized skill is rendered worthless
by new methods of production. Thus, the proletariat is recruited from all classes
of the population.
The proletariat goes through various stages of development. With its birth begins
its struggle with the bourgeoisie. At first, the contest is carried on by individual
laborers, then by the work of people of a factory, then by the operative of one trade,
in one locality, against the individual bourgeois who directly exploits them. They
direct their attacks not against the bourgeois condition of production, but against
the instruments of production themselves; they destroy imported wares that compete
with their labor, they smash to pieces machinery, they set factories ablaze, they
seek to restore by force the vanished status of the workman of the Middle Ages.
At this stage, the laborers still form an incoherent mass scattered over the whole
country, and broken up by their mutual competition. If anywhere they unite to form
more compact bodies, this is not yet the consequence of their own active union, but
of the union of the bourgeoisie, which class, in order to attain its own political
ends, is compelled to set the whole proletariat in motion, and is moreover yet, for
a time, able to do so. At this stage, therefore, the proletarians do not fight their
enemies, but the enemies of their enemies, the remnants of absolute monarchy, the
landowners, the non-industrial bourgeois, the petty bourgeois. Thus, the whole historical
movement is concentrated in the hands of the bourgeoisie; every victory so obtained
is a victory for the bourgeoisie.
But with the development of industry, the proletariat not only increases in number;
it becomes concentrated in greater masses, its strength grows, and it feels that strength
more. The various interests and conditions of life within the ranks of the proletariat
are more and more equalized, in proportion as machinery obliterates all distinctions
of labor, and nearly everywhere reduces wages to the same low level. The growing competition
among the bourgeois, and the resulting commercial crises, make the wages of the workers
ever more fluctuating. The increasing improvement of machinery, ever more rapidly
developing, makes their livelihood more and more precarious; the collisions between
individual workmen and individual bourgeois take more and more the character of collisions
between two classes. Thereupon, the workers begin to form combinations (trade unions)
against the bourgeois; they club together in order to keep up the rate of wages; they
found permanent associations in order to make provision beforehand for these occasional
revolts. Here and there, the contest breaks out into riots.
Now and then the workers are victorious, but only for a time. The real fruit of their
battles lie not in the immediate result, but in the ever expanding union of the workers.
This union is helped on by the improved means of communication that are created by
Modern Industry, and that place the workers of different localities in contact with
one another. It was just this contact that was needed to centralize the numerous local
struggles, all of the same character, into one national struggle between classes.
But every class struggle is a political struggle. And that union, to attain which
the burghers of the Middle Ages, with their miserable highways, required centuries,
the modern proletarian, thanks to railways, achieve in a few years.
This organization of the proletarians into a class, and, consequently, into a political
party, is continually being upset again by the competition between the workers themselves.
But it ever rises up again, stronger, firmer, mightier. It compels legislative recognition
of particular interests of the workers, by taking advantage of the divisions among
the bourgeoisie itself. Thus, the Ten-Hours Bill in England was carried.
Altogether, collisions between the classes of the old society further in many ways
the course of development of the proletariat. The bourgeoisie finds itself involved
in a constant battle. At first with the aristocracy; later on, with those portions
of the bourgeoisie itself, whose interests have become antagonistic to the progress
of industry; at all time with the bourgeoisie of foreign countries. In all these battles,
it sees itself compelled to appeal to the proletariat, to ask for help, and thus to
drag it into the political arena. The bourgeoisie itself, therefore, supplies the
proletariat with its own elements of political and general education, in other words,
it furnishes the proletariat with weapons for fighting the bourgeoisie.
Further, as we have already seen, entire sections of the ruling class are, by the
advance of industry, precipitated into the proletariat, or are at least threatened
in their conditions of existence. These also supply the proletariat with fresh elements
of enlightenment and progress.
Finally, in times when the class struggle nears the decisive hour, the progress of
dissolution going on within the ruling class, in fact within the whole range of old
society, assumes such a violent, glaring character, that a small section of the ruling
class cuts itself adrift, and joins the revolutionary class, the class that holds
the future in its hands. Just as, therefore, at an earlier period, a section of the
nobility went over to the bourgeoisie, so now a portion of the bourgeoisie goes over
to the proletariat, and in particular, a portion of the bourgeois ideologists, who
have raised themselves to the level of comprehending theoretically the historical
movement as a whole.
Of all the classes that stand face to face with the bourgeoisie today, the proletariat
alone is a genuinely revolutionary class. The other classes decay and finally disappear
in the face of Modern Industry; the proletariat is its special and essential product.
The lower middle class, the small manufacturer, the shopkeeper, the artisan, the
peasant, all these fight against the bourgeoisie, to save from extinction their existence
as fractions of the middle class. They are therefore not revolutionary, but conservative.
Nay, more, they are reactionary, for they try to roll back the wheel of history. If,
by chance, they are revolutionary, they are only so in view of their impending transfer
into the proletariat; they thus defend not their present, but their future interests;
they desert their own standpoint to place themselves at that of the proletariat.
The "dangerous class", the social scum, that passively rotting mass thrown off by
the lowest layers of the old society, may, here and there, be swept into the movement
by a proletarian revolution; its conditions of life, however, prepare it far more
for the part of a bribed tool of reactionary intrigue.
In the condition of the proletariat, those of old society at large are already virtually
swamped. The proletarian is without property; his relation to his wife and children
has no longer anything in common with the bourgeois family relations; modern industry
labor, modern subjection to capital, the same in England as in France, in America
as in Germany, has stripped him of every trace of national character. Law, morality,
religion, are to him so many bourgeois prejudices, behind which lurk in ambush just
as many bourgeois interests.
All the preceding classes that got the upper hand sought to fortify their already
acquired status by subjecting society at large to their conditions of appropriation.
The proletarians cannot become masters of the productive forces of society, except
by abolishing their own previous mode of appropriation, and thereby also every other
previous mode of appropriation. They have nothing of their own to secure and to fortify;
their mission is to destroy all previous securities for, and insurances of, individual
property.
All previous historical movements were movements of minorities, or in the interest
of minorities. The proletarian movement is the self-conscious, independent movement
of the immense majority, in the interest of the immense majority. The proletariat,
the lowest stratum of our present society, cannot stir, cannot raise itself up, without
the whole superincumbent strata of official society being sprung into the air.
Though not in substance, yet in form, the struggle of the proletariat with the bourgeoisie
is at first a national struggle. The proletariat of each country must, of course,
first of all settle matters with its own bourgeoisie.
In depicting the most general phases of the development of the proletariat, we traced
the more or less veiled civil war, raging within existing society, up to the point
where that war breaks out into open revolution, and where the violent overthrow of
the bourgeoisie lays the foundation for the sway of the proletariat.
Hitherto, every form of society has been based, as we have already seen, on the antagonism
of oppressing and oppressed classes. But in order to oppress a class, certain conditions
must be assured to it under which it can, at least, continue its slavish existence.
The serf, in the period of serfdom, raised himself to membership in the commune, just
as the petty bourgeois, under the yoke of the feudal absolutism, managed to develop
into a bourgeois. The modern laborer, on the contrary, instead of rising with the
process of industry, sinks deeper and deeper below the conditions of existence of
his own class. He becomes a pauper, and pauperism develops more rapidly than population
and wealth. And here it becomes evident that the bourgeoisie is unfit any longer to
be the ruling class in society, and to impose its conditions of existence upon society
as an overriding law. It is unfit to rule because it is incompetent to assure an existence
to its slave within his slavery, because it cannot help letting him sink into such
a state, that it has to feed him, instead of being fed by him. Society can no longer
live under this bourgeoisie, in other words, its existence is no longer compatible
with society.
The essential conditions for the existence and for the sway of the bourgeois class
is the formation and augmentation of capital; the condition for capital is wage labor.
Wage labor rests exclusively on competition between the laborers. The advance of industry,
whose involuntary promoter is the bourgeoisie, replaces the isolation of the laborers,
due to competition, by the revolutionary combination, due to association. The development
of Modern Industry, therefore, cuts from under its feet the very foundation on which
the bourgeoisie produces and appropriates products. What the bourgeoisie therefore
produces, above all, are its own grave-diggers. Its fall and the victory of the proletariat
are equally inevitable.
Footnotes
[1] By bourgeoisie is meant the class of modern capitalists, owners of the means
of social production and employers of wage labor.
By proletariat, the class of modern wage laborers who, having no means of production
of their own, are reduced to selling their labor power in order to live. [Note by
Engels - 1888 English edition]
[2] That is, all _written_ history. In 1847, the pre-history of society, the social
organization existing previous to recorded history, all but unknown. Since then, August
von Haxthausen (1792-1866) discovered common ownership of land in Russia, Georg Ludwig
von Maurer proved it to be the social foundation from which all Teutonic races started
in history, and, by and by, village communities were found to be, or to have been,
the primitive form of society everywhere from India to Ireland. The inner organization
of this primitive communistic society was laid bare, in its typical form, by Lewis
Henry Morgan's (1818-1861) crowning discovery of the true nature of the gens and its
relation to the tribe. With the dissolution of the primeaval communities, society
begins to be differentiated into separate and finally antagonistic classes. I have
attempted to retrace this dissolution in _Der Ursprung der
Familie, des Privateigenthumus und des Staats_, second edition, Stuttgart, 1886.
[Engels, 1888 English edition]
[3] Guild-master, that is, a full member of a guild, a master within, not a head
of a guild. [Engels: 1888 English edition]
[4] This was the name given their urban communities by the townsmen of Italy and
France, after they had purchased or conquered their initial rights of self-government
from their feudal lords. [Engels: 1890 German edition]
"Commune" was the name taken in France by the nascent towns even before they had
conquered from their feudal lords and masters local self-government and political
rights as the "Third Estate". Generally speaking, for the economical development of
the bourgeoisie, England is here taken as the typical country, for its political development,
France. [Engels: 1888 English edition]
Back to Top
II -- Proletarians And Communists
In what relation do the Communists stand to the proletarians as a whole? The Communists
do not form a separate party opposed to the other working-class parties.
They have no interests separate and apart from those of the proletariat as a whole.
They do not set up any sectarian principles of their own, by which to shape and mold
the proletarian movement.
The Communists are distinguished from the other working-class parties by this only:
(1) In the national struggles of the proletarians of the different countries, they
point out and bring to the front the common interests of the entire proletariat, independently
of all nationality.
(2) In the various stages of development which the struggle of the working class
against the bourgeoisie has to pass through, they always and everywhere represent
the interests of the movement as a whole.
The Communists, therefore, are on the one hand practically, the most advanced and
resolute section of the working-class parties of every country, that section which
pushes forward all others; on the other hand, theoretically, they have over the great
mass of the proletariat the advantage of clearly understanding the lines of march,
the conditions, and the ultimate general results of the proletarian movement.
The immediate aim of the Communists is the same as that of all other proletarian
parties: Formation of the proletariat into a class, overthrow of the bourgeois supremacy,
conquest of political power by the proletariat.
The theoretical conclusions of the Communists are in no way based on ideas or principles
that have been invented, or discovered, by this or that would-be universal reformer.
They merely express, in general terms, actual relations springing from an existing
class struggle, from a historical movement going on under our very eyes. The abolition
of existing property relations is not at all a distinctive feature of communism.
All property relations in the past have continually been subject to historical change
consequent upon the change in historical conditions.
The French Revolution, for example, abolished feudal property in favor of bourgeois
property.
The distinguishing feature of communism is not the abolition of property generally,
but the abolition of bourgeois property. But modern bourgeois private property is
the final and most complete expression of the system of producing and appropriating
products that is based on class antagonisms, on the exploitation of the many by the
few.
In this sense, the theory of the Communists may be summed up in the single sentence:
Abolition of private property.
We Communists have been reproached with the desire of abolishing the right of personally
acquiring property as the fruit of a man's own labor, which property is alleged to
be the groundwork of all personal freedom, activity and independence.
Hard-won, self-acquired, self-earned property! Do you mean the property of petty
artisan and of the small peasant, a form of property that preceded the bourgeois form?
There is no need to abolish that; the development of industry has to a great extent
already destroyed it, and is still destroying it daily.
Or do you mean the modern bourgeois private property?
But does wage labor create any property for the laborer? Not a bit. It creates capital,
i.e., that kind of property which exploits wage labor, and which cannot increase except
upon conditions of begetting a new supply of wage labor for fresh exploitation. Property,
in its present form, is based on the antagonism of capital and wage labor. Let us
examine both sides of this antagonism.
To be a capitalist, is to have not only a purely personal, but a social STATUS in
production. Capital is a collective product, and only by the united action of many
members, nay, in the last resort, only by the united action of all members of society,
can it be set in motion.
Capital is therefore not only personal; it is a social power.
When, therefore, capital is converted into common property, into the property of
all members of society, personal property is not thereby transformed into social property.
It is only the social character of the property that is changed. It loses its class
character.
Let us now take wage labor.
The average price of wage labor is the minimum wage, i.e., that quantum of the means
of subsistence which is absolutely requisite to keep the laborer in bare existence
as a laborer. What, therefore, the wage laborer appropriates by means of his labor
merely suffices to prolong and reproduce a bare existence. We by no means intend to
abolish this personal appropriation of the products of labor, an appropriation that
is made for the maintenance and reproduction of human life, and that leaves no surplus
wherewith to command the labor of others. All that we want to do away with is the
miserable character of this appropriation, under which the laborer lives merely to
increase capital, and is allowed to live only in so far as the interest of the ruling
class requires it.
In bourgeois society, living labor is but a means to increase accumulated labor.
In communist society, accumulated labor is but a means to widen, to enrich, to promote
the existence of the laborer.
In bourgeois society, therefore, the past dominates the present; in communist society,
the present dominates the past. In bourgeois society, capital is independent and has
individuality, while the living person is dependent and has no individuality.
And the abolition of this state of things is called by the bourgeois, abolition of
individuality and freedom! And rightly so. The abolition of bourgeois individuality,
bourgeois independence, and bourgeois freedom is undoubtedly aimed at.
By freedom is meant, under the present bourgeois conditions of production, free trade,
free selling and buying.
But if selling and buying disappears, free selling and buying disappears also. This
talk about free selling and buying, and all the other "brave words" of our bourgeois
about freedom in general, have a meaning, if any, only in contrast with restricted
selling and buying, with the fettered traders of the Middle Ages, but have no meaning
when opposed to the communist abolition of buying and selling, or the bourgeois conditions
of production, and of the bourgeoisie itself.
You are horrified at our intending to do away with private property. But in your
existing society, private property is already done away with for nine-tenths of the
population; its existence for the few is solely due to its non-existence in the hands
of those nine-tenths. You reproach us, therefore, with intending to do away with a
form of property, the necessary condition for whose existence is the non-existence
of any property for the immense majority of society.
In one word, you reproach us with intending to do away with your property. Precisely
so; that is just what we intend.
From the moment when labor can no longer be converted into capital, money, or rent,
into a social power capable of being monopolized, i.e., from the moment when individual
property can no longer be transformed into bourgeois property, into capital, from
that moment, you say, individuality vanishes.
You must, therefore, confess that by "individual" you mean no other person than the
bourgeois, than the middle-class owner of property. This person must, indeed, be swept
out of the way, and made impossible.
Communism deprives no man of the power to appropriate the products of society; all
that it does is to deprive him of the power to subjugate the labor of others by means
of such appropriations.
It has been objected that upon the abolition of private property, all work will cease,
and universal laziness will overtake us.
According to this, bourgeois society ought long ago to have gone to the dogs through
sheer idleness; for those who acquire anything, do not work. The whole of this objection
is but another expression of the tautology: There can no longer be any wage labor
when there is no longer any capital.
All objections urged against the communistic mode of producing and appropriating
material products, have, in the same way, been urged against the communistic mode
of producing and appropriating intellectual products. Just as to the bourgeois, the
disappearance of class property is the disappearance of production itself, so the
disappearance of class culture is to him identical with the disappearance of all culture.
That culture, the loss of which he laments, is, for the enormous majority, a mere
training to act as a machine.
But don't wrangle with us so long as you apply, to our intended abolition of bourgeois
property, the standard of your bourgeois notions of freedom, culture, law, etc. Your
very ideas are but the outgrowth of the conditions of your bourgeois production and
bourgeois property, just as your jurisprudence is but the will of your class made
into a law for all, a will whose essential character and direction are determined
by the economical conditions of existence of your class.
The selfish misconception that induces you to transform into eternal laws of nature
and of reason the social forms stringing from your present mode of production and
form of property -- historical relations that rise and disappear in the progress of
production -- this misconception you share with every ruling class that has preceded
you. What you see clearly in the case of ancient property, what you admit in the case
of feudal property, you are of course forbidden to admit in the case of your own bourgeois
form of property.
Abolition of the family! Even the most radical flare up at this infamous proposal
of the Communists.
On what foundation is the present family, the bourgeois family, based? On capital,
on private gain. In its completely developed form, this family exists only among the
bourgeoisie. But this state of things finds its complement in the practical absence
of the family among proletarians, and in public prostitution.
The bourgeois family will vanish as a matter of course when its complement vanishes,
and both will vanish with the vanishing of capital.
Do you charge us with wanting to stop the exploitation of children by their parents?
To this crime we plead guilty.
But, you say, we destroy the most hallowed of relations, when we replace home education
by social.
And your education! Is not that also social, and determined by the social conditions
under which you educate, by the intervention direct or indirect, of society, by means
of schools, etc.? The Communists have not intended the intervention of society in
education; they do but seek to alter the character of that intervention, and to rescue
education from the influence of the ruling class.
The bourgeois claptrap about the family and education, about the hallowed correlation
of parents and child, becomes all the more disgusting, the more, by the action of
Modern Industry, all the family ties among the proletarians are torn asunder, and
their children transformed into simple articles of commerce and instruments of labor.
But you Communists would introduce community of women, screams the bourgeoisie in
chorus.
The bourgeois sees his wife a mere instrument of production. He hears that the instruments
of production are to be exploited in common, and, naturally, can come to no other
conclusion that the lot of being common to all will likewise fall to the women.
He has not even a suspicion that the real point aimed at is to do away with the status
of women as mere instruments of production.
For the rest, nothing is more ridiculous than the virtuous indignation of our bourgeois
at the community of women which, they pretend, is to be openly and officially established
by the Communists. The Communists have no need to introduce free love; it has existed
almost from time immemorial.
Our bourgeois, not content with having wives and daughters of their proletarians
at their disposal, not to speak of common prostitutes, take the greatest pleasure
in seducing each other's wives. (Ah, those were the days!)
Bourgeois marriage is, in reality, a system of wives in common and thus, at the most,
what the Communists might possibly be reproached with is that they desire to introduce,
in substitution for a hypocritically concealed, an openly legalized system of free
love. For the rest, it is self-evident that the abolition of the present system of
production must bring with it the abolition of free love springing from that system,
i.e., of prostitution both public and private.
The Communists are further reproached with desiring to abolish countries and nationality.
The workers have no country. We cannot take from them what they have not got. Since
the proletariat must first of all acquire political supremacy, must rise to be the
leading class of the nation, must constitute itself the nation, it is, so far, itself
national, though not in the bourgeois sense of the word.
National differences and antagonism between peoples are daily more and more vanishing,
owing to the development of the bourgeoisie, to freedom of commerce, to the world
market, to uniformity in the mode of production and in the conditions of life corresponding
thereto.
The supremacy of the proletariat will cause them to vanish still faster. United action
of the leading civilized countries at least is one of the first conditions for the
emancipation of the proletariat.
In proportion as the exploitation of one individual by another will also be put an
end to, the exploitation of one nation by another will also be put an end to. In proportion
as the antagonism between classes within the nation vanishes, the hostility of one
nation to another will come to an end.
The charges against communism made from a religious, a philosophical and, generally,
from an ideological standpoint, are not deserving of serious examination.
Does it require deep intuition to comprehend that man's ideas, views, and conception,
in one word, man's consciousness, changes with every change in the conditions of his
material existence, in his social relations and in his social life?
What else does the history of ideas prove, than that intellectual production changes
its character in proportion as material production is changed? The ruling ideas of
each age have ever been the ideas of its ruling class.
When people speak of the ideas that revolutionize society, they do but express that
fact that within the old society the elements of a new one have been created, and
that the dissolution of the old ideas keeps even pace with the dissolution of the
old conditions of existence.
When the ancient world was in its last throes, the ancient religions were overcome
by Christianity. When Christian ideas succumbed in the eighteenth century to rationalist
ideas, feudal society fought its death battle with the then revolutionary bourgeoisie.
The ideas of religious liberty and freedom of conscience merely gave expression to
the sway of free competition within the domain of knowledge.
"Undoubtedly," it will be said, "religious, moral, philosophical, and juridicial
ideas have been modified in the course of historical development. But religion, morality,
philosophy, political science, and law, constantly survived this change."
"There are, besides, eternal truths, such as Freedom, Justice, etc., that are common
to all states of society. But communism abolishes eternal truths, it abolishes all
religion, and all morality, instead of constituting them on a new basis; it therefore
acts in contradiction to all past historical experience."
What does this accusation reduce itself to? The history of all past society has consisted
in the development of class antagonisms, antagonisms that assumed different forms
at different epochs.
But whatever form they may have taken, one fact is common to all past ages, viz.,
the exploitation of one part of society by the other. No wonder, then, that the social
consciousness of past ages, despite all the multiplicity and variety it displays,
moves within certain common forms, or general ideas, which cannot completely vanish
except with the total disappearance of class antagonisms.
The communist revolution is the most radical rupture with traditional relations;
no wonder that its development involved the most radical rupture with traditional
ideas.
But let us have done with the bourgeois objections to communism.
We have seen above that the first step in the revolution by the working class is
to raise the proletariat to the position of ruling class to win the battle of democracy.
The proletariat will use its political supremacy to wrest, by degree, all capital
from the bourgeoisie, to centralize all instruments of production in the hands of
the state, i.e., of the proletariat organized as the ruling class; and to increase
the total productive forces as rapidly as possible.
Of course, in the beginning, this cannot be effected except by means of despotic
inroads on the rights of property, and on the conditions of bourgeois production;
by means of measures, therefore, which appear economically insufficient and untenable,
but which, in the course of the movement, outstrip themselves, necessitate further
inroads upon the old social order, and are unavoidable as a means of entirely revolutionizing
the mode of production.
These measures will, of course, be different in different countries.
Nevertheless, in most advanced countries, the following will be pretty generally
applicable.
1. Abolition of property in land and application of all rents of land to public purposes.
2. A heavy progressive or graduated income tax.
3. Abolition of all rights of inheritance.
4. Confiscation of the property of all emigrants and rebels.
5. Centralization of credit in the banks of the state, by means of a national bank
with state capital and an exclusive monopoly.
6. Centralization of the means of communication and transport in he hands of the
state.
7. Extension of factories and instruments of production owned by the state; the bringing
into cultivation of waste lands, and the improvement of the soil generally in accordance
with a common plan.
8. Equal obligation of all to work. Establishment of industrial armies, especially
for agriculture.
9. Combination of agriculture with manufacturing industries; gradual abolition of
all the distinction between town and country by a more equable distribution of the
populace over the country.
10. Free education for all children in public schools. Abolition of children's factory
labor in its present form. Combination of education with industrial production, etc.
When, in the course of development, class distinctions have disappeared, and all
production has been concentrated in the hands of a vast association of the whole nation,
the public power will lose its political character. Political power, properly so called,
is merely the organized power of one class for oppressing another. If the proletariat
during its contest with the bourgeoisie is compelled, by the force of circumstances,
to organize itself as a class; if, by means of a revolution, it makes itself the ruling
class, and, as such, sweeps away by force the old conditions of production, then it
will, along with these conditions, have swept away the conditions for the existence
of class antagonisms and of classes generally, and will thereby have abolished its
own supremacy as a class.
In place of the old bourgeois society, with its classes and class antagonisms, we
shall have an association in which the free development of each is the condition for
the free development of all.
Back to Top
III -- SOCIALIST AND COMMUNIST LITERATURE
1. Reactionary Socialism
a. Feudal Socialism
Owing to their historical position, it became the vocation of the aristocracies of
France and England to write pamphlets against modern bourgeois society. In the French
Revolution of July 1830, and in the English reform agitation, these aristocracies
again succumbed to the hateful upstart. Thenceforth, a serious political struggle
was altogether out of the question. A literary battle alone remained possible. But
even in the domain of literature, the old cries of the restoration period had become
impossible. [1]
In order to arouse sympathy, the aristocracy was obliged to lose sight, apparently,
of its own interests, and to formulate its indictment against the bourgeoisie in the
interest of the exploited working class alone. Thus, the aristocracy took their revenge
by singing lampoons on their new masters and whispering in his ears sinister prophesies
of coming catastrophe.
In this way arose feudal socialism: half lamentation, half lampoon; half an echo
of the past, half menace of the future; at times, by its bitter, witty and incisive
criticism, striking the bourgeoisie to the very heart's core, but always ludicrous
in its effect, through total incapacity to comprehend the march of modern history.
The aristocracy, in order to rally the people to them, waved the proletarian alms-bag
in front for a banner. But the people, so often as it joined them, saw on their hindquarters
the old feudal coats of arms, and deserted with loud and irreverent laughter.
One section of the French Legitimists and "Young England" exhibited this spectacle:
In pointing out that their mode of exploitation was different to that of the bourgeoisie,
the feudalists forget that they exploited under circumstances and conditions that
were quite different and that are now antiquated. In showing that, under their rule,
the modern proletariat never existed, they forget that the modern bourgeoisie is the
necessary offspring of their own form of society.
For the rest, so little do they conceal the reactionary character of their criticism
that their chief accusation against the bourgeois amounts to this: that under the
bourgeois regime a class is being developed which is destined to cut up, root and
branch, the old order of society.
What they upbraid the bourgeoisie with is not so much that it creates a proletariat
as that it creates a _revolutionary_ proletariat.
In political practice, therefore, they join in all corrective measures against the
working class; and in ordinary life, despite their high falutin' phrases, they stoop
to pick up the golden apples dropped from the tree of industry, and to barter truth,
love, and honor, for traffic in wool, beetroot-sugar, and potato spirits. [2]
As the parson has ever gone hand in hand with the landlord, so has clerical socialism
with feudal socialism.
Nothing is easier than to give Christian asceticism a socialist tinge. Has not Christianity
declaimed against private property, against marriage, against the state? Has it not
preached in the place of these, charity and poverty, celibacy and mortification of
the flesh, monastic life and Mother Church? Christian socialism is but the holy water
with which the priest consecrates the heart-burnings of the aristocrat.
b. Petty-Bourgeois Socialism
The feudal aristocracy was not the only class that was ruined by the bourgeoisie,
not the only class whose conditions of existence pined and perished in the atmosphere
of modern bourgeois society. The medieval burgesses and the small peasant proprietors
were the precursors of the modern bourgeoisie. In those countries which are but little
developed, industrially and commercially, these two classes still vegetate side by
side with the rising bourgeoisie.
In countries where modern civilization has become fully developed, a new class of
petty bourgeois has been formed, fluctuating between proletariat and bourgeoisie,
and ever renewing itself a supplementary part of bourgeois society. The individual
members of this class, however, as being constantly hurled down into the proletariat
by the action of competition, and, as Modern Industry develops, they even see the
moment approaching when they will completely disappear as an independent section of
modern society, to be replaced in manufactures, agriculture and commerce, by overlookers,
bailiffs and shopmen.
In countries like France, where the peasants constitute far more than half of the
population, it was natural that writers who sided with the proletariat against the
bourgeoisie should use, in their criticism of the bourgeois regime, the standard of
the peasant and petty bourgeois, and from the standpoint of these intermediate classes,
should take up the cudgels for the working class. Thus arose petty-bourgeois socialism.
Sismondi was the head of this school, not only in France but also in England.
This school of socialism dissected with great acuteness the contradictions in the
conditions of modern production. It laid bare the hypocritical apologies of economists.
It proved, incontrovertibly, the disastrous effects of machinery and division of labor;
the concentration of capital and land in a few hands; overproduction and crises; it
pointed out the inevitable ruin of the petty bourgeois and peasant, the misery of
the proletariat, the anarchy in production, the crying inequalities in the distribution
of wealth, the industrial war of extermination between nations, the dissolution of
old moral bonds, of the old family relations, of the old nationalities.
In it positive aims, however, this form of socialism aspires either to restoring
the old means of production and of exchange, and with them the old property relations,
and the old society, or to cramping the modern means of production and of exchange
within the framework of the old property relations that have been, and were bound
to be, exploded by those means. In either case, it is both reactionary and Utopian.
Its last words are: corporate guilds for manufacture; patriarchal relations in agriculture.
Ultimately, when stubborn historical facts had dispersed all intoxicating effects
of self-deception, this form of socialism ended in a miserable hangover.
c. German or "True" Socialism
The socialist and communist literature of France, a literature that originated under
the pressure of a bourgeoisie in power, and that was the expressions of the struggle
against this power, was introduced into Germany at a time when the bourgeoisie in
that country had just begun its contest with feudal absolutism.
German philosophers, would-be philosophers, and beaux esprits (men of letters), eagerly
seized on this literature, only forgetting that when these writings immigrated from
France into Germany, French social conditions had not immigrated along with them.
In contact with German social conditions, this French literature lost all its immediate
practical significance and assumed a purely literary aspect. Thus, to the German philosophers
of the eighteenth century, the demands of the first French Revolution were nothing
more than the demands of "Practical Reason" in general, and the utterance of the will
of the revolutionary French bourgeoisie signified, in their eyes, the laws of pure
will, of will as it was bound to be, of true human will generally.
The work of the German literati consisted solely in bringing the new French ideas
into harmony with their ancient philosophical conscience, or rather, in annexing the
French ideas without deserting their own philosophic point of view.
This annexation took place in the same way in which a foreign language is appropriated,
namely, by translation.
It is well known how the monks wrote silly lives of Catholic saints _over_ the manuscripts
on which the classical works of ancient heathendom had been written. The German literati
reversed this process with the profane French literature. They wrote their philosophical
nonsense beneath the French original. For instance, beneath the French criticism of
the economic functions of money, they wrote "alienation of humanity", and beneath
the French criticism of the bourgeois state they wrote "dethronement of the category
of the general", and so forth.
The introduction of these philosophical phrases at the back of the French historical
criticisms, they dubbed "Philosophy of Action", "True Socialism", "German Science
of Socialism", "Philosophical Foundation of Socialism", and so on.
The French socialist and communist literature was thus completely emasculated. And,
since it ceased, in the hands of the German, to express the struggle of one class
with the other, he felt conscious of having overcome "French one-sidedness" and of
representing, not true requirements, but the requirements of truth; not the interests
of the proletariat, but the interests of human nature, of man in general, who belongs
to no class, has no reality, who exists only in the misty realm of philosophical fantasy.
This German socialism, which took its schoolboy task so seriously and solemnly, and
extolled its poor stock-in-trade in such a mountebank fashion, meanwhile gradually
lost its pedantic innocence.
The fight of the Germans, and especially of the Prussian bourgeoisie, against feudal
aristocracy and absolute monarchy, in other words, the liberal movement, became more
earnest.
By this, the long-wished for opportunity was offered to "True" Socialism of confronting
the political movement with the socialistic demands, of hurling the traditional anathemas
against liberalism, against representative government, against bourgeois competition,
bourgeois freedom of the press, bourgeois legislation, bourgeois liberty and equality,
and of preaching to the masses that they had nothing to gain, and everything to lose,
by this bourgeois movement. German socialism forgot, in the nick of time, that the
French criticism, whose silly echo it was, presupposed the existence of modern bourgeois
society, with its corresponding economic conditions of existence, and the political
constitution adapted thereto, the very things those attainment was the object of the
pending struggle in Germany.
To the absolute governments, with their following of parsons, professors, country
squires, and officials, it served as a welcome scarecrow against the threatening bourgeoisie.
It was a sweet finish, after the bitter pills of flogging and bullets, with which
these same governments, just at that time, dosed the German working-class risings.
While this "True" Socialism thus served the government as a weapon for fighting the
German bourgeoisie, it, at the same time, directly represented a reactionary interest,
the interest of German philistines. In Germany, the petty-bourgeois class, a relic
of the sixteenth century, and since then constantly cropping up again under the various
forms, is the real social basis of the existing state of things.
To preserve this class is to preserve the existing state of things in Germany. The
industrial and political supremacy of the bourgeoisie threatens it with certain destruction
-- on the one hand, from the concentration of capital; on the other, from the rise
of a revolutionary proletariat. "True" Socialism appeared to kill these two birds
with one stone. It spread like an epidemic.
The robe of speculative cobwebs, embroidered with flowers of rhetoric, steeped in
the dew of sickly sentiment, this transcendental robe in which the German Socialists
wrapped their sorry "eternal truths", all skin and bone, served to wonderfully increase
the sale of their goods amongst such a public. And on its part German socialism recognized,
more and more, its own calling as the bombastic representative of the petty-bourgeois
philistine.
It proclaimed the German nation to be the model nation, and the German petty philistine
to be the typical man. To every villainous meanness of this model man, it gave a hidden,
higher, socialistic interpretation, the exact contrary of its real character. It went
to the extreme length of directly opposing the "brutally destructive" tendency of
communism, and of proclaiming its supreme and impartial contempt of all class struggles.
With very few exceptions, all the so-called socialist and communist publications that
now (1847) circulate in Germany belong to the domain of this foul and enervating literature.
[3]
2. Conservative Or Bourgeois Socialism
A part of the bourgeoisie is desirous of redressing social grievances in order to
secure the continued existence of bourgeois society.
To this section belong economists, philanthropists, humanitarians, improvers of the
condition of the working class, organizers of charity, members of societies for the
prevention of cruelty to animals, temperance fanatics, hole-and-corner reformers of
every imaginable kind. This form of socialism has, moreover, been worked out into
complete systems.
We may cite Proudhon's Philosophy of Poverty as an example of this form.
The socialistic bourgeois want all the advantages of modern social conditions without
the struggles and dangers necessarily resulting therefrom. They desire the existing
state of society, minus its revolutionary and disintegrating elements. They wish for
a bourgeoisie without a proletariat. The bourgeoisie naturally conceives the world
in which it is supreme to be the best; and bourgeois socialism develops this comfortable
conception into various more or less complete systems. In requiring the proletariat
to carry out such a system, and thereby to march straightaway into the social New
Jerusalem, it but requires in reality that the proletariat should remain within the
bounds of existing society, but should cast away all its hateful ideas concerning
the bourgeoisie.
A second, and more practical, but less systematic, form of this socialism sought
to depreciate every revolutionary movement in the eyes of the working class by showing
that no mere political reform, but only a change in the material conditions of existence,
in economical relations, could be of any advantage to them. By changes in the material
conditions of existence, this form of socialism, however, by no means understands
abolition of the bourgeois relations of production, an abolition that can be affected
only by a revolution, but administrative reforms, based on the continued existence
of these relations; reforms, therefore, that in no respect affect the relations between
capital and labor, but, at the best, lessen the cost, and simplify the administrative
work of bourgeois government.
Bourgeois socialism attains adequate expression when, and only when, it becomes a
mere figure of speech.
Free trade: for the benefit of the working class. Protective duties: for the benefit
of the working class. Prison reform: for the benefit of the working class. This is
the last word and the only seriously meant word of bourgeois socialism.
It is summed up in the phrase: the bourgeois is a bourgeois -- for the benefit of
the working class.
3. Critical-Utopian Socialism And Communism
We do not here refer to that literature which, in every great modern revolution,
has always given voice to the demands of the proletariat, such as the writings of
Babeuf [4] and others.
The first direct attempts of the proletariat to attain its own ends, made in times
of universal excitement, when feudal society was being overthrown, necessarily failed,
owing to the then undeveloped state of the proletariat, as well as to the absence
of the economic conditions for its emancipation, conditions that had yet to be produced,
and could be produced by the impending bourgeois epoch alone. The revolutionary literature
that accompanied these first movements of the proletariat had necessarily a reactionary
character. It inculcated universal asceticism and social levelling in its crudest
form.
The socialist and communist systems, properly so called, those of Saint-Simon [5],
Fourier [6], Owen [7], and others, spring into existence in the early undeveloped
period, described above, of the struggle between proletariat and bourgeoisie (see
Section 1. Bourgeois and Proletarians).
The founders of these systems see, indeed, the class antagonisms, as well as the
action of the decomposing elements in the prevailing form of society. But the proletariat,
as yet in its infancy, offers to them the spectacle of a class without any historical
initiative or any independent political movement.
Since the development of class antagonism keeps even pace with the development of
industry, the economic situation, as they find it, does not as yet offer to them the
material conditions for the emancipation of the proletariat. They therefore search
after a new social science, after new social laws, that are to create these conditions.
Historical action is to yield to their personal inventive action; historically created
conditions of emancipation to fantastic ones; and the gradual, spontaneous class organization
of the proletariat to an organization of society especially contrived by these inventors.
Future history resolves itself, in their eyes, into the propaganda and the practical
carrying out of their social plans.
In the formation of their plans, they are conscious of caring chiefly for the interests
of the working class, as being the most suffering class. Only from the point of view
of being the most suffering class does the proletariat exist for them.
The undeveloped state of the class struggle, as well as their own surroundings, causes
Socialists of this kind to consider themselves far superior to all class antagonisms.
They want to improve the condition of every member of society, even that of the most
favored. Hence, they habitually appeal to society at large, without the distinction
of class; nay, by preference, to the ruling class. For how can people when once they
understand their system, fail to see in it the best possible plan of the best possible
state of society?
Hence, they reject all political, and especially all revolutionary action; they wish
to attain their ends by peaceful means, necessarily doomed to failure, and by the
force of example, to pave the way for the new social gospel.
Such fantastic pictures of future society, painted at a time when the proletariat
is still in a very undeveloped state and has but a fantastic conception of its own
position, correspond with the first instinctive yearnings of that class for a general
reconstruction of society.
But these socialist and communist publications contain also a critical element. They
attack every principle of existing society. Hence, they are full of the most valuable
materials for the enlightenment of the working class. The practical measures proposed
in them -- such as the abolition of the distinction between town and country, of the
family, of the carrying on of industries for the account of private individuals, and
of the wage system, the proclamation of social harmony, the conversion of the function
of the state into a more superintendence of production -- all these proposals point
solely to the disappearance of class antagonisms which were, at that time, only just
cropping up, and which, in these publications, are recognized in their earliest indistinct
and undefined forms only. These proposals, therefore, are of a purely utopian character.
The significance of critical-utopian socialism and communism bears an inverse relation
to historical development. In proportion as the modern class struggle develops and
takes definite shape, this fantastic standing apart from the contest, these fantastic
attacks on it, lose all practical value and all theoretical justifications. Therefore,
although the originators of these systems were, in many respects, revolutionary, their
disciples have, in every case, formed mere reactionary sects. They hold fast by the
original views of their masters, in opposition to the progressive historical development
of the proletariat. They, therefore, endeavor, and that consistently, to deaden the
class struggle and to reconcile the class antagonisms. They still dream of experimental
realization of their social utopias, of founding isolated phalansteres, of establishing
"Home Colonies", or setting up a "Little Icaria" [8] -- pocket editions of the New
Jerusalem -- and to realize all these castles in the air, they are compelled to appeal
to the feelings and purses of the bourgeois. By degrees, they sink into the category
of the reactionary conservative socialists depicted above, differing from these only
by more systematic pedantry, and by their fanatical and superstitious belief in the
miraculous effects of their social science.
They, therefore, violently oppose all political action on the part of the working
class; such action, according to them, can only result from blind unbelief in the
new gospel.
The Owenites in England, and the Fourierists in France, respectively, oppose the
Chartists and the Reformistes.
Footnotes
[1] Note by Engels to 1888 English edition: Not the English Restoration (1660-1689),
but the French Restoration (1814-1830).
[2] Note by Engels to 1888 English edition: This applies chiefly to Germany, where
the landed aristocracy and squirearchy have large portions of their estates cultivated
for their own account by stewards, and are, moreover, extensive beetroot-sugar manufacturers
and distillers of potato spirits. The wealthier british aristocracy are, as yet, rather
above that; but they, too, know how to make up for declining rents by lending their
names to floaters or more or less shady joint-stock companies.
[3] Note by Engels to 1888 German edition: The revolutionary storm of 1848 swept
away this whole shabby tendency and cured its protagonists of the desire to dabble
in socialism. The chief representative and classical type of this tendency is Mr Karl
Gruen.
[4] Francois Noel Babeuf (1760-1797): French political agitator; plotted unsuccessfully
to destroy the Directory in revolutionary France and established a communistic system.
[5] Comte de Saint-Simon, Claude Henri de Rouvroy (1760-1825): French social philosopher;
generally regarded as founder of French socialism. He thought society should be reorganized
along industrial lines and that scientists should be the new spiritual leaders. His
most important work is _Nouveau_Christianisme_ (1825).
[6] Charles Fourier (1772-1837): French social reformer; propounded a system of self-sufficient
cooperatives known as Fourierism, especially in his work _Le_Nouveau_Monde_industriel_
(1829-30)
[7] Richard Owen (1771-1858): Welsh industrialist and social reformer. He formed
a model industrial community at New Lanark, Scotland, and pioneered cooperative societies.
His books include _New_View_Of_Society_ (1813).
[8] Note by Engels to 1888 English edition: "Home Colonies" were what Owen called
his communist model societies. _Phalansteres_ were socialist colonies on the plan
of Charles Fourier; Icaria was the name given by Caber to his utopia and, later on,
to his American communist colony.
IV -- Position Of The Communists In Relation To
The Various Existing Opposition Parties
Section II has made clear the relations of the Communists to the existing working-class
parties, such as the Chartists in England and the Agrarian Reformers in America.
The Communists fight for the attainment of the immediate aims, for the enforcement
of the momentary interests of the working class; but in the movement of the present,
they also represent and take care of the future of that movement. In France, the Communists
ally with the Social Democrats* against the conservative and radical bourgeoisie,
reserving, however, the right to take up a critical position in regard to phases and
illusions traditionally handed down from the Great Revolution.
In Switzerland, they support the Radicals, without losing sight of the fact that
this party consists of antagonistic elements, partly of Democratic Socialists, in
the French sense, partly of radical bourgeois.
In Poland, they support the party that insists on an agrarian revolution as the prime
condition for national emancipation, that party which fomented the insurrection of
Krakow in 1846.
In Germany, they fight with the bourgeoisie whenever it acts in a revolutionary way,
against the absolute monarchy, the feudal squirearchy, and the petty-bourgeoisie.
But they never cease, for a single instant, to instill into the working class the
clearest possible recognition of the hostile antagonism between bourgeoisie and proletariat,
in order that the German workers may straightway use, as so many weapons against the
bourgeoisie, the social and political conditions that the bourgeoisie must necessarily
introduce along with its supremacy, and in order that, after the fall of the reactionary
classes in Germany, the fight against the bourgeoisie itself may immediately begin.
The Communists turn their attention chiefly to Germany, because that country is on
the eve of a bourgeois revolution that is bound to be carried out under more advanced
conditions of European civilization and with a much more developed proletariat than
that of England was in the seventeenth, and France in the eighteenth century, and
because the bourgeois revolution in Germany will be but the prelude to an immediately
following proletarian revolution.
In short, the Communists everywhere support every revolutionary movement against
the existing social and political order of things.
In all these movements, they bring to the front, as the leading question in each,
the property question, no matter what its degree of development at the time.
Finally, they labor everywhere for the union and agreement of the democratic parties
of all countries.
The Communists disdain to conceal their views and aims. They openly declare that
their ends can be attained only by the forcible overthrow of all existing social conditions.
Let the ruling classes tremble at a communist revolution. The proletarians have nothing
to lose but their chains. They have a world to win.
Proletarians of all countries, unite!
Footnotes
* NOTE by Engels to 1888 English edition: The party then represented in Parliament
by Ledru-Rollin, in literature by Louis Blanc (1811-82), in the daily press by the
Reforme. The name of Social-Democracy signifies, with these its inventors, a section
of the Democratic or Republican Party more or less tinged with socialism.
Back to Top
Preface To 1872 German Edition
The Communist League, an international association of workers, which could of course
be only a secret one, under conditions obtaining at the time, commissioned us, the
undersigned, at the Congress held in London in November 1847, to write for publication
a detailed theoretical and practical programme for the Party. Such was the origin
of the following Manifesto, the manuscript of which travelled to London to be printed
a few weeks before the February Revolution. First published in German, it has been
republished in that language in at least twelve different editions in Germany, England,
and America. It was published in English for the first time in 1850 in the _Red Republican_,
London, translated by Miss Helen Macfarlane, and in 1871 in at least three different
translations in America. The french version first appeared in Paris shortly before
the June insurrection of 1848, and recently in _Le Socialiste_ of New York. A new
translation is in the course of preparation. A Polish version appeared in London shortly
after it was first published in Germany. A Russian translation was published in Geneva
in the 'sixties. Into Danish, too, it was translated shortly after its appearance.
However much that state of things may have altered during the last twenty-five years,
the general principles laid down in the Manifesto are, on the whole, as correct today
as ever. Here and there, some detail might be improved. The practical application
of the principles will depend, as the Manifesto itself states, everywhere and at all
times, on the historical conditions for the time being existing, and, for that reason,
no special stress is laid on the revolutionary measures proposed at the end of Section
II. That passage would, in many respects, be very differently worded today. In view
of the gigantic strides of Modern Industry since 1848, and of the accompanying improved
and extended organization of the working class, in view of the practical experience
gained, first in the February Revolution, and then, still more, in the Paris Commune,
where the proletariat for the first time held political power for two whole months,
this programme has in some details been antiquated. One thing especially was proved
by the Commune, viz., that "the working class cannot simply lay hold of ready-made
state machinery, and wield it for its own purposes." (See The Civil War in France:
Address of the General Council of the International Working Men's Assocation, 1871,
where this point is further developed.) Further, it is self-evident that the criticism
of socialist literature is deficient in relation to the present time, because it comes
down only to 1847; also that the remarks on the relation of the Communists to the
various opposition parties (Section IV), although, in principle still correct, yet
in practice are antiquated, because the political situation has been entirely changed,
and the progress of history has swept from off the earth the greater portion of the
political parties there enumerated.
But then, the Manifesto has become a historical document which we have no longer
any right to alter. A subsequent edition may perhaps appear with an introduction bridging
the gap from 1847 to the present day; but this reprint was too unexpected to leave
us time for that.
Karl Marx
Frederick Engels
June 24, 1872
London
Back to Top
Preface To 1882 Russian Edition
The first Russian edition of the Manifesto of the Communist Party, translated by
Bakunin, was published early in the 'sixties by the printing office of the Kolokol.
Then the West could see in it (the Russian edition of the Manifesto) only a literary
curiosity. Such a view would be impossible today.
What a limited field the proletarian movement occupied at that time (December 1847)
is most clearly shown by the last section: the position of the Communists in relation
to the various opposition parties in various countries. Precisely Russia and the United
States are missing here. It was the time when Russia constituted the last great reserve
of all European reaction, when the United States absorbed the surplus proletarian
forces of Europe through immigration. Both countries provided Europe with raw materials
and were at the same time markets for the sale of its industrial products. Bother
were, therefore, in one way of another, pillars of the existing European system.
How very different today. Precisely European immigration fitted North American for
a gigantic agricultural production, whose competition is shaking the very foundations
of European landed property -- large and small. At the same time, it enabled the United
States to exploit its tremendous industrial resources with an energy and on a scale
that must shortly break the industrial monopoly of Western Europe, and especially
of England, existing up to now. Both circumstances react in a revolutionary manner
upon America itself. Step by step, the small and middle land ownership of the farmers,
the basis of the whole political constitution, is succumbing to the competition of
giant farms; at the same time, a mass industrial proletariat and a fabulous concentration
of capital funds are developing for the first time in the industrial regions.
And now Russia! During the Revolution of 1848-9, not only the European princes, but
the European bourgeois as well, found their only salvation from the proletariat just
beginning to awaken in Russian intervention. The Tsar was proclaimed the chief of
European reaction. Today, he is a prisoner of war of the revolution in Gatchina, and
Russia forms the vanguard of revolutionary action in Europe.
The Communist Manifesto had, as its object, the proclamation of the inevitable impending
dissolution of modern bourgeois property. But in Russia we find, face-to-face with
the rapidly flowering capitalist swindle and bourgeois property, just beginning to
develop, more than half the land owned in common by the peasants. Now the question
is: can the Russian obshchina, though greatly undermined, yet a form of primeaval
common ownership of land, pass directly to the higher form of Communist common ownership?
Or, on the contrary, must it first pass through the same process of dissolution such
as constitutes the historical evolution of the West?
The only answer to that possible today is this: If the Russian Revolution becomes
the signal for a proletarian revolution in the West, so that both complement each
other, the present Russian common ownership of land may serve as the starting point
for a communist development.
Karl Marx
Frederick Engels January 21, 1882
London
Back to Top
Reface To 1883 German Edition
The preface to the present edition I must, alas, sign alone. Marx, the man to whom
the whole working class class of Europe and America owes more than to any one else
-- rests at Highgate Cemetary and over his grave the first first grass is already
growing. Since his death [March 13, 1883], there can be even less thought of revising
or supplementing the Manifesto. But I consider it all the more necessary again to
state the following expressly:
The basic thought running through the Manifesto -- that economic production, and
the structure of society of every historical epoch necessarily arising therefrom,
constitute the foundation for the political and intellectual history of that epoch;
that consequently (ever since the dissolution of the primaeval communal ownership
of land) all history has been a history of class struggles, of struggles between exploited
and exploiting, between dominated and dominating classes at various stages of social
evolution; that this struggle, however, has now reached a stage where the exploited
and oppressed class (the proletariat) can no longer emancipate itself from the class
which exploits and oppresses it (the bourgeoisie), without at the same time forever
freeing the whole of society from exploitation, oppression, class struggles -- this
basic thought belongs soley and exclusively to Marx.
[Engels Footnote To Paragraph: "This proposition", I wrote in the preface to the
English translation, "which, in my opinion, is destined to do for history what Darwin's
theory has done for biology, we both of us, had been gradually approaching for some
years before 1845. How far I had independently progressed towards it is best shown
by my _Conditions of the Working Class in England_. But when I again met Marx at Brussels,
in spring 1845, he had it already worked out and put it before me in terms almost
as clear as those in which I have stated it here."]
I have already stated this many times; but precisely now is it necessary that it
also stand in front of the Manifesto itself.
Frederick Engels
June 28, 1883
London
Back to Top
Preface To 1888 English Edition
The Manifesto was published as the platform of the Communist League, a working men's
association, first exclusively German, later on international, and under the political
conditions of the Continent before 1848, unavoidably a secret society. At a Congress
of the League, held in November 1847, Marx and Engels were commissioned to prepare
a complete theoretical and practical party programme. Drawn up in German, in January
1848, the manuscript was sent to the printer in London a few weeks before the French
Revolution of February 24. A French translation was brought out in Paris shortly before
the insurrection of June 1848. The first English translation, by Miss Helen Macfarlane,
appeared in George Julian Harney's _Red Republican_, London, 1850. A Danish and a
Polish edition had also been published.
The defeat of the Parisian insurrection of June 1848 -- the first great battle between
proletariat and bourgeoisie -- drove again into the background, for a time, the social
and political aspirations of the European working class. Thenceforth, the struggle
for supremacy was, again, as it had been before the Revolution of February, solely
between different sections of the propertied class; the working class was reduced
to a fight for political elbow-room, and to the position of extreme wing of the middle-class
Radicals. Wherever independent proletarian movements continued to show signs of life,
they were ruthlessly hunted down. Thus the Prussian police hunted out the Central
Board of the Communist League, then located in Cologne. The members were arrested
and, after eighteen months' imprisonment, they were tried in October 1852. This selebrated
"Cologne Communist Trial" lasted from October 4 till November 12; seven of the prisoners
were sentenced to terms of imprisonment in a fortress, varying from three to six years.
Immediately after the sentence, the League was formlly dissolved by the remaining
members. As to the Manifesto, it seemed henceforth doomed to oblivion.
When the European workers had recovered sufficient strength for another attack on
the ruling classes, the International Working Men's Association sprang up. But this
association, formed with the express aim of welding into one body the whole militant
proletariat of Europe and America, could not at once proclaim the principles laid
down in the Manifesto. The International was bound to have a programme broad enough
to be acceptable to the English trade unions, to the followers of Proudhon in France,
Belgium, Italy, and Spain, and to the Lassalleans in Germany.
[ENGEL'S FOOTNOTE: Lassalle personally, to us, always acknowledged himself to be
a disciple of Marx, and, as such, stood on the ground of the Manifesto. But in his
first public agitation, 1862-1864, he did not go beyond demanding co-operative worhsops
supported by state credit.]
Marx, who drew up this programme to the satisfaction of all parties, entirely trusted
to the intellectual development of the working class, which was sure to result from
combined action and mutual discussion. The very events and vicissitudes in the struggle
against capital, the defeats even more than the victories, could not help bringing
home to men's minds the insufficiency of their various favorite nostrums, and preparing
the way for a more complete insight into the true conditions for working-class emancipation.
And Marx was right. The International, on its breaking in 1874, left the workers quite
different men from what it found them in 1864. Proudhonism in France, Lassalleanism
in Germany, were dying out, and even the conservative English trade unions, though
most of them had long since severed their connection with the International, were
gradually advancing towards that point at which, last year at Swansea, their president
could say in their name: "Continental socialism has lost its terror for us." In fact,
the principles of the Manifesto had made considerable headway among the working men
of all countries.
The Manifesto itself came thus to the front again. Since 1850, the German text had
been reprinted several times in Switzerland, England, and America. In 1872, it was
translated into English in New York, where the translation was published in _Woorhull
and Claflin's Weekly_. From this English version, a French one was made in _Le Socialiste_
of New York. Since then, at least two more English translations, moer or less mutilated,
have been brought out in America, and one of them has been reprinted in England. The
first Russian translation, made by Bakunin, was published at Herzen's Kolokol office
in Geneva, about 1863; a second one, by the heroic Vera Zasulich, also in Geneva,
in 1882. A new Danish edition is to be found in _Socialdemokratisk Bibliothek_, Copenhagen,
1885; a fresh French translation in _Le Socialiste_, Paris, 1886. From this latter,
a Spanish version was prepared and published in Madrid, 1886. The German reprints
are not to be counted; there have been twelve altogether at the least. An Armenian
translation, which was to be published in Constantinople some months ago, did not
see the light, I am told, because the publisher was afraid of bringing out a book
with the name of Marx on it, while the translator declined to call it his own production.
Of further translations into other languages I have heard but had not seen. Thus the
history of the Manifesto reflects the history of the modern working-class movement;
at present, it is doubtless the most wide spread, the most international production
of all socialist literature, the common platform acknowledged by millions of working
men from Siberia to California.
Yet, when it was written, we could not have called it a _socialist_ manifesto. By
Socialists, in 1847, were understood, on the one hand the adherents of the various
Utopian systems: Owenites in England, Fourierists in France, both of them already
reduced to the position of mere sects, and gradually dying out; on the other hand,
the most multifarious social quacks who, by all manner of tinkering, professed to
redress, without any danger to capital and profit, all sorts of social grievances,
in both cases men outside the working-class movement, and looking rather to the "educated"
classes for support. Whatever portion of the working class had become convinced of
the insufficiency of mere political revolutions, and had proclaimed the necessity
of total social change, called itself Communist. It was a crude, rough-hewn, purely
instinctive sort of communism; still, it touched the cardinal point and was powerful
enough amongst the working class to produce the Utopian communism of Cabet in France,
and of Weitling in Germany. Thus, in 1847, socialism was a middle-class movement,
communism a working-class movement. Socialism was, on the Continent at least, "respectable";
communism was the very opposite. And as our notion, from the very beginning, was that
"the emancipation of the workers must be the act of the working class itself," there
could be no doubt as to which of the two names we must take. Moreover, we have, ever
since, been far from repudiating it.
The Manifesto being our joint production, I consider myself bound to state that the
fundamental proposition which forms the nucleus belongs to Marx. That proposition
is: That in every historical epoch, th prevailing mode of economic production and
exchange, and the social organization necessarily following from it, form the basis
upon which it is built up, and from that which alone can be explained the political
and intellectual history of that epoch; that consequently the whole history of mankind
(since the dissolution of primitive tribal society, holding land in common ownership)
has been a history of class struggles, contests between exploiting and exploited,
ruling and oppressed classes; That the history of these class struggles forms a series
of evolutions in which, nowadays, a stage has been reached where the exploited and
oppressed class -- the proletariat -- cannot attain its emancipation from the sway
of the exploiting and ruling class -- the bourgeoisie -- without, at the same time,
and once and for all, emancipating society at large from all exploitation, oppression,
class distinction, and class struggles.
This proposition, which, in my opinion, is destined to do for history what Darwin's
theory has done for biology, we both of us, had been gradually approaching for some
years before 1845. How far I had independently progressed towards it is best shown
by my _Conditions of the Working Class in England_. But when I again met Marx at Brussels,
in spring 1845, he had it already worked out and put it before me in terms almost
as clear as those in which I have stated it here.
From our joint preface to the German edition of 1872, I quote the following:
"However much that state of things may have altered during the last twenty-five years,
the general principles laid down in the Manifesto are, on the whole, as correct today
as ever. Here and there, some detail might be improved. The practical application
of the principles will depend, as the Manifesto itself states, everywhere and at all
times, on the historical conditions for the time being existing, and, for that reason,
no special stress is laid on the revolutionary measures proposed at the end of Section
II. That passage would, in many respects, be very differently worded today. In view
of the gigantic strides of Modern Industry since 1848, and of the accompanying improved
and extended organization of the working class, in view of the practical experience
gained, first in the February Revolution, and then, still more, in the Paris Commune,
where the proletariat for the first time held political power for two whole months,
this programme has in some details been antiquated. One thing especially was proved
by the Commune, viz., that "the working class cannot simply lay hold of ready-made
state machinery, and wield it for its own purposes." (See _The Civil War in France:
Address of the General Council of the International Working Men's Assocation_ 1871,
where this point is further developed.) Further, it is self-evident that the criticism
of socialist literature is deficient in relation to the present time, because it comes
down only to 1847; also that the remarks on the relation of the Communists to the
various opposition parties (Section IV), although, in principle still correct, yet
in practice are antiquated, because the political situation has been entirely changed,
and the progress of history has swept from off the Earth the greater portion of the
political parties there enumerated.
"But then, the Manifesto has become a historical document which we have no longer
any right to alter."
The present translation is by Mr Samuel Moore, the translator of the greater portion
of Marx's _Capital_. We have revised it in common, and I have added a few notes explanatory
of historical allusions.
Frederick Engels
January 30, 1888
London
Back to Top
Preface To 1890 German Edition
Since [the 1883 German edition preface] was written, a new German edition of the
Manifesto has again become necessary, and much has also happened to the Manifesto
which should be recorded here.
A second Russian translation -- by Vera Zasulich -- appeared in Geneva in 1882; the
preface to that edition was written by Marx and myself. Unfortunately, the original
German manuscript has gone astray; I must therefore retranslate from the Russian which
will in no way improve the text. It reads:
"The first Russian edition of the Manifesto of the Communist Party, translated by
Bakunin, was published early in the 'sixties by the printing office of the Kolokol.
Then the West could see in it (the Russian edition of the Manifesto) only a literary
curiosity. Such a view would be impossible today.
"What a limited field the proletarian movement occupied at that time (December 1847)
is most clearly shown by the last section: the position of the Communists in relation
to the various opposition parties in various countries. Precisely Russia and the United
States are missing here. It was the time when Russia constituted the last great reserve
of all European reaction, when the United States absorbed the surplus proletarian
forces of Europe through immigration. Both countries provided Europe with raw materials
and were at the same time markets for the sale of its industrial products. Both were,
therefore, in one way of another, pillars of the existing European system.
"How very different today. Precisely European immigration fitted North American for
a gigantic agricultural production, whose competition is shaking the very foundations
of European landed property -- large and small. At the same time, it enabled the United
States to exploit its tremendous industrial resources with an energy and on a scale
that must shortly break the industrial monopoly of Western Europe, and especially
of England, existing up to now. Both circumstances react in a revolutionary manner
upon America itself. Step by step, the small and middle land ownership of the farmers,
the basis of the whole political constitution, is succumbing to the competition of
giant farms; at the same time, a mass industrial proletariat and a fabulous concentration
of capital funds are developing for the first time in the industrial regions.
"And now Russia! During the Revolution of 1848-9, not only the European princes,
but the European bourgeois as well, found their only salvation from the proletariat
just beginning to awaken in Russian intervention. The Tsar was proclaimed the chief
of European reaction. Today, he is a prisoner of war of the revolution in Gatchina,
and Russia forms the vanguard of revolutionary action in Europe.
"The Communist Manifesto had, as its object, the proclamation of the inevitable impending
dissolution of modern bourgeois property. But in Russia we find, face-to-face with
the rapidly flowering capitalist swindle and bourgeois property, just beginning to
develop, more than half the land owned in common by the peasants. Now the question
is: can the Russian obshchina, though greatly undermined, yet a form of primeaval
common ownership of land, pass directly to the higher form of Communist common ownership?
Or, on the contrary, must it first pass through the same process of dissolution such
as constitutes the historical evolution of the West?
"The only answer to that possible today is this: If the Russian Revolution becomes
the signal for a proletarian revolution in the West, so that both complement each
other, the present Russian common ownership of land may serve as the starting point
for a communist development.
"January 21, 1882 London"
At about the same date, a new Polish version appeared in Geneva: _Manifest Kommunistyczny_.
Furthermore, a new Danish translation has appeared in the _Socialdemokratisk Bibliothek_,
Copenhagen, 1885. Unfortunately, it is not quite complete; certain essential passages,
which seem to have presented difficulties to the translator, have been omitted, and,
in addition, there are saigns of carelessness here and there, which are all the more
unpleasantly conspicuous since the translation indicates that had the translator taken
a little more pains, he would have done an excellent piece of work.
A new French version appeared in 1886, in _Le Socialiste_ of Paris; it is the best
published to date.
From this latter, a Spanish version was published the same year in _El Socialista_
of Madrid, and then reissued in pamphlet form: _Manifesto del Partido Communista_
por Carlos Marx y F. Engels, Madrid, Administracion de El Socialista, Hernan Cortes
8.
As a matter of curiosity, I may mention that in 1887 the manuscript of an Armenian
translation was offered to a publisher in Constantinople. But the good man did not
have the courage to publish something bearing the name of Marx and suggested that
the translator set down his own name as author, which the latter however declined.
After one, and then another, of the more or less inaccurate American translations
had been repeatedly reprinted in England, an authentic version at last appeared in
1888. This was my friend Samuel Moore, and we went through it together once more before
it went to press. It is entitled: _Manifesto of the Communist_Party_, by Karl Marx
and Frederick Engels. Authorized English translation, edited and annotated by Frederick
Engels, 1888, London, William Reeves, 185 Fleet Street, E.C. I have added some of
the notes of that edition to the present one.
The Manifesto has had a history of its own. Greeted with enthusiasm, at the time
of its appearance, by the not at all numerous vanguard of scientific socialism (as
is proved by the translations mentioned in the first place), it was soon forced into
the background by the reaction that began with the defeat of the Paris workers in
June 1848, and was finally excommunicated "by law" in the conviction of the Cologne
Communists in November 1852. With the disappearance from the public scene of the workers'
movement that had begun with the February Revolution, the Manifesto too passed into
the background.
When the European workers had again gathered sufficient strength for a new onslaught
upon the power of the ruling classes, the International Working Men's Association
came into being. Its aim was to weld together into _one_ huge army the whole militant
working class of Europe and America. Therefore it could not _set out_ from the principles
laid down in the Manifesto. It was bound to have a programme which would not shut
the door on the English trade unions, the French, Belgian, Italian, and Spanish Proudhonists,
and the German Lassalleans. This programme -- the considerations underlying the Statutes
of the International -- was drawn up by Marx with a master hand acknowledged even
by the Bakunin and the anarchists. For the ultimate final triumph of the ideas set
forth in the Manifesto, Marx relied solely upon the intellectual development of the
working class, as it necessarily has to ensue from united action and discussion. The
events and vicissitudes in the struggle against capital, the defeats even more than
the successes, could not but demonstrate to the fighters the inadequacy of their former
universal panaceas, and make their minds more receptive to a thorough understanding
of the true conditions for working-class emancipation. And Marx was right. The working
class of 1874, at the dissolution of the International, was altogether different from
that of 1864, at its foundation. Proudhonism in the Latin countries, and the specific
Lassalleanism in Germany, were dying out; and even the ten arch-conservative English
trade unions were gradually approaching the point where, in 1887, the chairman of
their Swansea Congress could say in their name: "Continental socialism has lost its
terror for us." Yet by 1887 continental socialism was almost exclusively the theory
heralded in the Manifesto. Thus, to a certain extent, the history of the Manifesto
reflects the history of the modern working-class movement since 1848. At present,
it is doubtless the most widely circulated, the most international product of all
socialist literature, the common programme of many millions of workers of all countries
from Siberia to California.
Nevertheless, when it appeared, we could not have called it a _socialist_ manifesto.
In 1847, two kinds of people were considered socialists. On the one hand were the
adherents of the various utopian systems, notably the Owenites in England and the
Fourierists in France, both of whom, at that date, had already dwindled to mere sects
gradually dying out. On the other, the manifold types of social quacks who wanted
to eliminate social abuses through their various universal panaceas and all kinds
of patch-work, without hurting capital and profit in the least. In both cases, people
who stood outside the labor movement and who looked for support rather to the "educated"
classes. The section of the working class, however, which demanded a radical reconstruction
of society, convinced that mere political revolutions were not enough, then called
itself _Communist_. It was still a rough-hewn, only instinctive and frequently somewhat
crude communism. Yet, it was powerful enough to bring into being two systems of utopian
communism -- in France, the "Icarian" communists of Cabet, and in Germany that of
Weitling. Socialism in 1847 signified a bourgeois movement, communism a working-class
movement. Socialism was, on the Continent at least, quite respectable, whereas communism
was the very opposite. And since we were very decidely of the opinion as early as
then that "the emancipation of the workers must be the task of the working class itself,"
we could have no hesitation as to which of the two names we should choose. Nor has
it ever occured to us to repudiate it.
"Working men of all countries, unite!" But few voices responded when we proclaimed
these words to the world 42 years ago, on the eve of the first Paris Revolution in
which the proletariat came out with the demands of its own. On September 28, 1864,
however, the proletarians of most of the Western European countries joined hands in
the International Working Men's Association of glorious memory. True, the International
itself lived only nine years. But that the eternal union of the proletarians of all
countries created by it is still alive and lives stronger than ever, there is no better
witness than this day. Because today, as I write these lines, the European and American
proletariat is reviewing its fighting forces, mobilized for the first time, mobilized
as _one_ army, under _one_ flag, for _one_ immediate aim: the standard eight-hour
working day to be established by legal enactment, as proclaimed by the Geneva Congress
of the International in 1866, and again by the Paris Workers' Congress of 1889. And
today's spectacle will open the eyes of the capitalists and landlords of all countries
to the fact that today the proletarians of all countries are united indeed.
If only Marx were still by my side to see this with his own eyes!
Frederick Engels
May 1, 1890
London
Notes On The Manifesto And Translations Of It
The Communist Manifesto was first published in February 1848 in London. It was written
by Marx and Engels for the Communist League, an organisation of German emigre workers
living in several western European countries. The translation above follows that of
the authorised English translation by Samuel Moore of 1888. In a few places, notably
the concluding line 'Proletarians of all countries, unite!, Hal Draper's 1994 translation
has been followed, rather than Moore's, which read ''Working men of all countries
unite!' For an exceptionally thorough account of the background of the Manifesto,
the history of different editions and translations, see Hal Draper The Adventures
of the Communist Manifesto Centre for Socialist History, Berkeley 1994.
Back to Top