Constitutional Law Cases: Rehnquist Court
1990 - 1999
U.S. Supreme Court
Syllabus
VACCO, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF NEW YORK, et al. v. QUILL et al.
certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the second circuit
No. 95-1858.
Argued January 8, 1997
Decided June 26, 1997
In New York, as in most States, it is a crime to aid another to commit or attempt
suicide, but patients may refuse even lifesaving medical treatment. Respondent New
York physicians assert that, although it would be consistent with the standards of
their medical practices to prescribe lethal medication for mentally competent, terminally
ill patients who are suffering great pain and desire a doctor's help in taking their
own lives, they are deterred from doing so by New York's assisted suicide ban. They,
and three gravely ill patients who have since died, sued the State's Attorney General,
claiming that the ban violates the Fourteenth Amendment's Equal Protection Clause.
The Federal District Court disagreed, but the Second Circuit reversed, holding (1)
that New York accords different treatment to those competent, terminally ill persons
who wish to hasten their deaths by self administering prescribed drugs than it does
to those who wish to do so by directing the removal of life support systems, and (2)
that this supposed unequal treatment is not rationally related to any legitimate state
interests.
Held: New York's prohibition on assisting suicide does not violate the Equal Protection
Clause. Pp. 3-14.
(a) The Equal Protection Clause embodies a general rule that States must treat like
cases alike but may treat unlike cases accordingly. E.g., Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S.
202, 216 . The New York statutes outlawing assisted suicide neither infringe fundamental
rights nor involve suspect classifications, e.g., Washington v. Glucksberg, ante,
at 14-24, and are therefore entitled to a strong presumption of validity, Heller v.
Doe, 509 U.S. 312, 319 . On their faces, neither the assisted suicide ban nor the
law permitting patients to refuse medicaltreatment treats anyone differently from
anyone else or draws any distinctions between persons. Everyone, regardless of physical
condition, is entitled, if competent, to refuse unwanted lifesaving medical treatment;
no one is permitted to assist a suicide. Generally, laws that apply evenhandedly to
all unquestionably comply with equal protection. E.g., New York City Transit Authority
v. Beazer, 440 U.S. 568, 587 . This Court disagrees with the Second Circuit's submission
that ending or refusing lifesaving medical treatment "is nothing more nor less than
assisted suicide." The distinction between letting a patient die and making that patient
die is important, logical, rational, and well established: It comports with fundamental
legal principles of causation, see, e.g., People v. Kevorkian, 447 Mich. 436, 470-472,
527 N. W. 2d 714, 728, cert. denied, 514 U.S. 1083 , and intent, see, e.g., United
States v. Bailey, 444 U.S. 394, 403 -406; has been recognized, at least implicitly,
by this Court in Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dept. of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 278 -280;
id., at 287-288 (O'Connor, J., concurring); and has been widely recognized and endorsed
in the medical profession, the state courts, and the overwhelming majority of state
legislatures, which, like New York's, have permitted the former while prohibiting
the latter. The Court therefore disagrees with respondents' claim that the distinction
is "arbitrary" and "irrational." The line between the two acts may not always be clear,
but certainty is not required, even were it possible. Logic and contemporary practice
support New York's judgment that the two acts are different, and New York may therefore,
consistent with the Constitution, treat them differently. Pp. 3-13.
(b) New York's reasons for recognizing and acting on the distinction between refusing
treatment and assisting a suicide--including prohibiting intentional killing and preserving
life; preventing suicide; maintaining physicians' role as their patients' healers;
protecting vulnerable people from indifference, prejudice, and psychological and financial
pressure to end their lives; and avoiding a possible slide towards euthanasia--are
valid and important public interests that easily satisfy the constitutional requirement
that a legislative classification bear a rational relation to some legitimate end.
See Glucksberg, ante. Pp. 13-14.
80 F. 3d 716, reversed.
Rehnquist, C. J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which O'Connor, Scalia,
Kennedy, and Thomas, JJ., joined. O'Connor, J., filed a concurring opinion, in which
Ginsburg and Breyer, JJ., joined in part. Stevens, J., Souter, J., Ginsburg, J., and
Breyer, J., filed opinions concurring in the judgment.
----------------------------------------------------------------------------
NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the preliminary
print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of
Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Wash ington, D.C. 20543, of any typographical
or other formal errors, in order that corrections may be made before the preliminary
print goes to press.
U.S. Supreme Court
No. 95-1858
DENNIS C. VACCO, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF NEW YORK, et al., PETITIONERS v. TIMOTHY E.
QUILL et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 26, 1997]
Chief Justice Rehnquist delivered the opinion of the Court.
In New York, as in most States, it is a crime to aid another to commit or attempt
suicide, 1 but patients may refuse even lifesaving medical treatment. 2 The question
presented by this case is whether New York's prohibition on assisting suicide therefore
violates the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. We hold that it
does not.
Petitioners are various New York public officials. Respondents Timothy E. Quill,
Samuel C. Klagsbrun, and Howard A. Grossman are physicians who practice in New York.
They assert that although it would be "consistent with the standards of [their] medical
practice[s]" to prescribe lethal medication for "mentally competent, terminally ill
patients" who are suffering great pain and desire a doctor's help in taking their
own lives, they are deterred from doing so by New York's ban on assisting suicide.
App. 25-26. 3 Respondents, and three gravely ill patients who have since died, 4 sued
the State's Attorney General in the United States District Court. They urged that
because New York permits a competent person to refuse life sustaining medical treatment,
and because the refusal of such treatment is "essentially the same thing" as physician
assisted suicide, New York's assisted suicide ban violates the Equal Protection Clause.
Quill v. Koppell, 870 F. Supp. 78, 84-85 (SDNY 1994).
The District Court disagreed: "[I]t is hardly unreasonable or irrational for the
State to recognize a difference between allowing nature to take its course, even in
the most severe situations, and intentionally using an artificial death producing
device." Id., at 84. The court noted New York's "obvious legitimate interests in preserving
life, and in protecting vulnerable persons,"and concluded that "[u]nder the United
States Constitution and the federal system it establishes, the resolution of this
issue is left to the normal democratic processes within the State." Id., at 84-85.
The Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit reversed. 80 F. 3d 716 (1996). The court
determined that, despite the assisted suicide ban's apparent general applicability,
"New York law does not treat equally all competent persons who are in the final stages
of fatal illness and wish to hasten their deaths," because "those in the final stages
of terminal illness who are on life support systems are allowed to hasten their deaths
by directing the removal of such systems; but those who are similarly situated, except
for the previous attachment of life sustaining equipment, are not allowed to hasten
death by self administering prescribed drugs." Id., at 727, 729. In the court's view,
"[t]he ending of life by [the withdrawal of life support systems] is nothing more
nor less than assisted suicide." Id., at 729 (emphasis added) (citation omitted).
The Court of Appeals then examined whether this supposed unequal treatment was rationally
related to any legitimate state interests, 5 and concluded that "to the extent that
[New York's statutes] prohibit a physician from prescribing medications to be self
administered by a mentally competent, terminally ill person in the final stages of
his terminal illness, they are not rationally related to any legitimate state interest."
Id., at 731. We granted certiorari, 518 U. S. ___ (1996), and now reverse.
The Equal Protection Clause commands that no State shall "deny to any person within
its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws." This provision creates nosubstantive
rights. San Antonio Independent School Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1, 33 (1973);
id., at 59 (Stewart, J., concurring). Instead, it embodies a general rule that States
must treat like cases alike but may treat unlike cases accordingly. Plyler v. Doe,
457 U.S. 202, 216 (1982) (" `[T]he Constitution does not require things which are
different in fact or opinion to be treated in law as though they were the same' ")
(quoting Tigner v. Texas, 310 U.S. 141, 147 (1940)). If a legislative classification
or distinction "neither burdens a fundamental right nor targets a suspect class, we
will uphold [it] so long as it bears a rational relation to some legitimate end."
Romer v. Evans, 517 U. S. ___, ___ (slip op., at 10) (1996).
New York's statutes outlawing assisting suicide affect and address matters of profound
significance to all New Yorkers alike. They neither infringe fundamental rights nor
involve suspect classifications. Washington v. Glucksberg, ante, at 15-24; see 80
F. 3d, at 726; San Antonio School Dist., 411 U.S., at 28 ("The system of alleged discrimination
and the class it defines have none of the traditional indicia of suspectness"); id.,
at 33-35 (courts must look to the Constitution, not the "importance" of the asserted
right, when deciding whether an asserted right is "fundamental"). These laws are therefore
entitled to a "strong presumption of validity." Heller v. Doe, 509 U.S. 312, 319 (1993).
On their faces, neither New York's ban on assisting suicide nor its statutes permitting
patients to refuse medical treatment treat anyone differently than anyone else or
draw any distinctions between persons. Everyone, regardless of physical condition,
is entitled, if competent, to refuse unwanted lifesaving medical treatment; no one
is permitted to assist a suicide. Generally speaking, laws that apply evenhandedly
to all "unquestionably comply" with the Equal Protection Clause. New York City Transit
Authority v. Beazer, 440 U.S. 568, 587 (1979); see Personnel Administrator of Mass.
v. Feeney, 442 U.S. 256, 271 -273 (1979) ("[M]any [laws] affect certain groups unevenly,
even though the law itself treats them no differently from all other members of the
class described by the law").
The Court of Appeals, however, concluded that some terminally ill people--those who
are on life support systems--are treated differently than those who are not, in that
the former may "hasten death" by ending treatment, but the latter may not "hasten
death" through physician assisted suicide. 80 F. 3d, at 729. This conclusion depends
on the submission that ending or refusing lifesaving medical treatment "is nothing
more nor less than assisted suicide." Ibid. Unlike the Court of Appeals, we think
the distinction between assisting suicide and withdrawing life sustaining treatment,
a distinction widely recognized and endorsed in the medical profession 6 and in our
legal traditions, is bothimportant and logical; it is certainly rational. See Feeney,
supra, at 272 ("When the basic classification is rationally based, uneven effects
upon particular groups within a class are ordinarily of no constitutional concern").
The distinction comports with fundamental legal principles of causation and intent.
First, when a patient refuses life sustaining medical treatment, he dies from an underlying
fatal disease or pathology; but if a patient ingests lethal medication prescribed
by a physician, he is killed by that medication. See, e.g., People v. Kevorkian, 447
Mich. 436, 470-472, 527 N. W. 2d 714, 728 (1994), cert. denied, 514 U.S. 1083 (1995);
Matter of Conroy, 98 N. J. 321, 355, 486 A. 2d 1209, 1226 (1985) (when feeding tube
is removed, death "result[s] . . . from [the patient's] underlying medical condition");
In re Colyer, 99 Wash. 2d 114, 123, 660 P. 2d 738, 743 (1983) ("[D]eath which occurs
after the removal of life sustaining systems is from natural causes"); American Medical
Association, Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, Physician Assisted Suicide,
10 Issues in Law & Medicine 91, 92 (1994) ("When a life sustaining treatment is declined,
the patient dies primarily because of an underlying disease").
Furthermore, a physician who withdraws, or honors a patient's refusal to begin, life
sustaining medical treatment purposefully intends, or may so intend, only to respect
his patient's wishes and "to cease doing useless and futile or degrading things to
the patient when [the patient] no longer stands to benefit from them." Assisted Suicide
in the United States, Hearing before the Subcommittee on the Constitution of the House
Committee on the Judiciary, 104th Cong., 2d Sess., 368 (1996) (testimony of Dr. Leon
R. Kass). The same is true when a doctor provides aggressive palliative care; in some
cases, painkilling drugs may hasten a patient's death, but the physician's purpose
and intent is, or maybe, only to ease his patient's pain. A doctor who assists a suicide,
however, "must, necessarily and indubitably, intend primarily that the patient be
made dead." Id., at 367. Similarly, a patient who commits suicide with a doctor's
aid necessarily has the specific intent to end his or her own life, while a patient
who refuses or discontinues treatment might not. See, e.g., Matter of Conroy, supra,
at 351, 486 A. 2d, at 1224 (patients who refuse life sustaining treatment "may not
harbor a specific intent to die" and may instead "fervently wish to live, but to do
so free of unwanted medical technology, surgery, or drugs"); Superintendent of Belchertown
State School v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 743, n. 11, 370 N. E. 2d 417, 426, n. 11
(1977) ("[I]n refusing treatment the patient may not have the specific intent to die").
The law has long used actors' intent or purpose to distinguish between two acts that
may have the same result. See, e.g., United States v. Bailey, 444 U.S. 394, 403 -406
(1980) ("[T]he . . . common law of homicide often distinguishes . . . between a person
who knows that another person will be killed as the result of his conduct and a person
who acts with the specific purpose of taking another's life"); Morissette v. United
States, 342 U.S. 246, 250 (1952) (distinctions based on intent are "universal and
persistent in mature systems of law"); M. Hale, 1 Pleas of the Crown 412 (1847) ("If
A., with an intent to prevent gangrene beginning in his hand doth without any advice
cut off his hand, by which he dies, he is not thereby felo de se for tho it was a
voluntary act, yet it was not with an intent to kill himself"). Put differently, the
law distinguishes actions taken "because of" a given end from actions taken "in spite
of" their unintended but foreseen consequences. Feeney, 442 U.S., at 279 ; Compassion
in Dying v. Washington, 79 F. 3d 790, 858 (CA9 1996) (Kleinfeld, J., dissenting) (%When
General Eisenhower ordered American soldiers onto the beaches of Normandy, he knew
that he wassending many American soldiers to certain death . . . . His purpose, though,
was to . . . liberate Europe from the Nazis").
Given these general principles, it is not surprising that many courts, including
New York courts, have carefully distinguished refusing life sustaining treatment from
suicide. See, e.g., Fosmire v. Nicoleau, 75 N. Y. 2d 218, 227, and n. 2, 551 N. E.
2d 77, 82, and n. 2 (1990) ("[M]erely declining medical . . . care is not considered
a suicidal act"). 7 In fact, the first state court decision explicitly to authorize
withdrawing lifesaving treatment noted the "real distinction between the self infliction
of deadly harm and a self determination against artificial life support." In re Quinlan,
70 N. J. 10, 43, 52, and n. 9, 355 A. 2d 647, 665, 670, and n. 9, cert. denied sub
nom. Garger v. New Jersey, 429 U.S. 922 (1976). And recently, the Michigan Supreme
Court also rejected the argument that the distinction "between acts that artificially
sustain life and acts that artificially curtail life" is merely a "distinction without
constitutional significance--a meaningless exercise in semantic gymnastics," insisting
that "the Cruzan majority disagreed and so do we." Kevorkian, 447 Mich., at 471, 527
N. W. 2d, at 728. 8
Similarly, the overwhelming majority of state legislatures have drawn a clear line
between assisting suicide and withdrawing or permitting the refusal of unwanted lifesaving
medical treatment by prohibiting the former and permitting the latter. Glucksberg,
ante, at 4-6, 11-15. And "nearly all states expressly disapprove ofsuicide and assisted
suicide either in statutes dealing with durable powers of attorney in health care
situations, or in `living will' statutes." Kevorkian, 447 Mich., at 478-479, and nn.
53-54, 527 N. W. 2d, at 731-732, and nn. 53-54. 9 Thus, even as the States move toprotect
and promote patients' dignity at the end of life, they remain opposed to physician
assisted suicide.
New York is a case in point. The State enacted its current assisted suicide statutes
in 1965. 10 Since then, New York has acted several times to protect patients' common
law right to refuse treatment. Act of Aug. 7, 1987, ch. 818, §1, 1987 N. Y. Laws 3140
("Do Not Resuscitate Orders") (codified as amended at N. Y. Pub. Health Law §§2960-2979
(McKinney 1994 and Supp. 1997)); Act of July 22, 1990, ch. 752, §2, 1990 N. Y. Laws
3547 ("Health Care Agents and Proxies") (codified as amended at N. Y. Pub. Health
Law §§2980-2994 (McKinney 1994 and Supp. 1997)). In so doing, however, the State has
neither endorsed a general right to "hasten death" nor approved physician assisted
suicide. Quite the opposite: The State has reaffirmed the line between "killing" and
"letting die." See N. Y. Pub. Health Law §2989(3) (McKinney 1994) ("This article is
not intended to permit or promote suicide, assisted suicide, or euthanasia"); New
York State Task Force on Life and the Law, Life Sustaining Treatment: Making Decisions
and Appointing a Health Care Agent 36-42 (July 1987); Do Not Resuscitate Orders: The
Proposed Legislation and Report of the New York State Task Force on Life and the Law
15 (Apr. 1986). More recently, the New York State Task Force on Life and the Law studied
assisted suicide and euthanasia and, in1994, unanimously recommended against legalization.
When Death is Sought: Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in the Medical Context vii (1994).
In the Task Force's view, "allowing decisions to forego life sustaining treatment
and allowing assisted suicide or euthanasia have radically different consequences
and meanings for public policy." Id., at 146.
This Court has also recognized, at least implicitly, the distinction between letting
a patient die and making that patient die. In Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dept. of Health,
497 U.S. 261, 278 (1990), we concluded that "[t]he principle that a competent person
has a constitutionally protected liberty interest in refusing unwanted medical treatment
may be inferred from our prior decisions," and we assumed the existence of such a
right for purposes of that case, id., at 279. But our assumption of a right to refuse
treatment was grounded not, as the Court of Appeals supposed, on the proposition that
patients have a general and abstract "right to hasten death," 80 F. 3d, at 727-728,
but on well established, traditional rights to bodily integrity and freedom from unwanted
touching, Cruzan, 497 U.S., at 278 -279; id., at 287-288 (O'Connor, J., concurring).
In fact, we observed that "the majority of States in this country have laws imposing
criminal penalties on one who assists another to commit suicide." Id., at 280. Cruzan
therefore provides no support for the notion that refusing life sustaining medical
treatment is "nothing more nor less than suicide."
For all these reasons, we disagree with respondents' claim that the distinction between
refusing lifesaving medical treatment and assisted suicide is "arbitrary" and "irrational."
Brief for Respondents 44. 11 Granted, insome cases, the line between the two may not
be clear, but certainty is not required, even were it possible. 12 Logic and contemporary
practice support New York's judgment that the two acts are different, and New York
may therefore, consistent with the Constitution, treat them differently. By permitting
everyone to refuse unwanted medical treatment while prohibiting anyone from assisting
a suicide, New York law follows a longstanding and rational distinction.
New York's reasons for recognizing and acting on this distinction--including prohibiting
intentional killing and preserving life; preventing suicide; maintainingphysicians'
role as their patients' healers; protecting vulnerable people from indifference, prejudice,
and psychological and financial pressure to end their lives; and avoiding a possible
slide towards euthanasia--are discussed in greater detail in our opinion in Glucksberg,
ante. These valid and important public interests easily satisfy the constitutional
requirement that a legislative classification bear a rational relation to some legitimate
end. 13
The judgment of the Court of Appeals is reversed.
It is so ordered.
----------------------------------------------------------------------------
U.S. Supreme Court
Nos. 96-110 and 95-1858
WASHINGTON, et al., PETITIONERS 96-110 v. HAROLD GLUCKSBERG et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the ninth circuit
DENNIS C. VACCO, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF NEW YORK, et al., PETITIONERS
95-1858v.
TIMOTHY E. QUILL et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 26, 1997]
Justice O'Connor, concurring. *
Death will be different for each of us. For many, the last days will be spent in
physical pain and perhaps the despair that accompanies physical deterioration and
a loss of control of basic bodily and mental functions. Some will seek medication
to alleviate that pain and other symptoms.
The Court frames the issue in this case as whether the Due Process Clause of the
Constitution protects a "right to commit suicide which itself includes a right to
assistance in doing so," ante, at 18, and concludes that
our Nation's history, legal traditions, and practices do not support the existence
of such a right. I join the Court's opinions because I agree that there is no generalized
right to "commit suicide." But respondents urge us to address the narrower question
whether a mentally competent person who is experiencing great suffering has a constitutionally
cognizable interest in controlling the circumstances of his or her imminent death.
I see no need to reach that question in the context of the facial challenges to the
New York and Washington laws at issue here. See ante, at 18 ("The Washington statute
at issue in this case prohibits `aid[ing] another person to attempt suicide,'. . .
and, thus, the question before us is whether the `liberty' specially protected by
the Due Process Clause includes a right to commit suicide which itself includes a
right to assistance in doing so"). The parties and amici agree that in these States
a patient who is suffering from a terminal illness and who is experiencing great pain
has no legal barriers to obtaining medication, from qualified physicians, to alleviate
that suffering, even to the point of causing unconsciousness and hastening death.
See Wash. Rev. Code §70.122.010 (1994); Brief for Petitioners in No. 95-1858, p. 15,
n. 9; Brief for Respondents in No. 95-1858, p. 15. In this light, even assuming that
we would recognize such an interest, I agree that the State's interests in protecting
those who are not truly competent or facing imminent death, or those whose decisions
to hasten death would not truly be voluntary, are sufficiently weighty to justify
a prohibition against physician assisted suicide. Ante, at 27-30; post, at 11 (Stevens,
J., concurring in judgments); post, at 33-39 (Souter, J., concurring in judgment).
Every one of us at some point may be affected by our own or a family member's terminal
illness. There is no reason to think the democratic process will not strike the proper
balance between the interests of terminallyill, mentally competent individuals who
would seek to end their suffering and the State's interests in protecting those who
might seek to end life mistakenly or under pressure. As the Court recognizes, States
are presently undertaking extensive and serious evaluation of physician assisted suicide
and other related issues. Ante, at 11, 12-13; see post, at 36-39 (Souter, J., concurring
in judgment). In such circumstances, "the . . . challenging task of crafting appropriate
procedures for safeguarding . . . liberty interests is entrusted to the `laboratory'
of the States . . . in the first instance." Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dept. of Health,
497 U.S. 261, 292 (1990) (O'Connor, J., concurring) (citing New State Ice Co. v. Liebmann,
285 U.S. 262, 311 (1932)).
In sum, there is no need to address the question whether suffering patients have
a constitutionally cognizable interest in obtaining relief from the suffering that
they may experience in the last days of their lives. There is no dispute that dying
patients in Washington and New York can obtain palliative care, even when doing so
would hasten their deaths. The difficulty in defining terminal illness and the risk
that a dying patient's request for assistance in ending his or her life might not
be truly voluntary justifies the prohibitions on assisted suicide we uphold here.
----------------------------------------------------------------------------
U.S. Supreme Court
Nos. 96-110 and 95-1858
WASHINGTON, et al., PETITIONERS 96-110 v. HAROLD GLUCKSBERG et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the ninth circuit
DENNIS C. VACCO, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF NEW YORK, et al., PETITIONERS
95-1858v.
TIMOTHY E. QUILL et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 26, 1997]
Justice Stevens, concurring in the judgments.
The Court ends its opinion with the important observation that our holding today
is fully consistent with a continuation of the vigorous debate about the "morality,
legality, and practicality of physician assisted suicide" in a democratic society.
Ante, at 32. I write separately to make it clear that there is also room for further
debate about the limits that the Constitution places on the power of the States to
punish the practice.
The morality, legality, and practicality of capital punishment have been the subject
of debate for many years. In 1976, this Court upheld the constitutionality of the
practice in cases coming to us from Georgia, 1 Florida 2 , and Texas. 3 In those cases
we concluded that a State does have the power to place a lesser value on some lives
than on others; there is no absolute requirement that a State treat all human life
as having an equal right to preservation. Because the state legislatures had sufficiently
narrowed the category of lives that the State could terminate, and had enacted special
procedures to ensure that the defendant belonged in that limited category, we concluded
that the statutes were not unconstitutional on their face. In later cases coming to
us from each of those States, however, we found that some applications of the statutes
were unconstitutional. 4
Today, the Court decides that Washington's statute prohibiting assisted suicide is
not invalid "on its face," that is to say, in all or most cases in which it might
be applied. 5 That holding, however, does not foreclose the possibility that some
applications of the statute might well be invalid.
As originally filed, this case presented a challenge to the Washington statute on
its face and as it applied to three terminally ill, mentally competent patients and
to four physicians who treat terminally ill patients. After the District Court issued
its opinion holding that the statute placed an undue burden on the right to commit
physician assisted suicide, see Compassion in Dying v. Washington, 850 F. Supp. 1454,
1462, 1465 (WD Wash. 1994), the three patients died. Although the Court of Appeals
considered the constitutionality of the statute-as applied to the prescription of
life ending medication for use by terminally ill, competent adult patients who wish
to hasten their deaths," Compassion in Dying v. Washington, 79 F. 3d 790, 798 (CA9
1996), the court did not have before it any individual plaintiff seeking to hasten
her death or any doctor who was threatened with prosecution for assisting in the suicide
of a particular patient; its analysis and eventual holding that the statute was unconstitutional
was not limited to a particular set of plaintiffs before it.
The appropriate standard to be applied in cases making facial challenges to state
statutes has been the subject of debate within this Court. See Janklow v. Planned
Parenthood, Sioux Falls Clinic, 517 U. S. ___ (1996). Upholding the validity of the
federal Bail Reform Act of 1984, the Court stated in United States v. Salerno, 481
U.S. 739 (1987), that a "facial challenge to a legislative Act is, of course, the
most difficult challenge to mount successfully, since the challenger must establish
that no set of circumstances exists under which the Act would be valid." Id., at 745.
6 I do not believe the Court has ever actually applied such a strict standard, 7 even
in Salerno itself, and the Court does not appear to apply Salerno here. Nevertheless,
the Court does conceive of respondents' claim as a facial challenge--addressing not
the application of the statute to a particular set of plaintiffs before it, but the
constitutionality of the statute's categorical prohibition against "aid[ing] another
person to attempt suicide." Ante, at 18 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing
Wash. Rev. Code §9A.36.060(1) (1994)). Accordingly, the Court requires the plaintiffs
to show that the interest in liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment "includes
a right to commit suicide which itself includes a right to assistance in doing so."
Ante, at 18.
History and tradition provide ample support for refusing to recognize an open ended
constitutional right to commit suicide. Much more than the State's paternalistic interest
in protecting the individual from the irrevocable consequences of an ill advised decision
motivated by temporary concerns is at stake. There is truth in John Donne's observation
that "No man is an island." 8 The State has an interest in preserving and fostering
the benefits that every human being may provide to the community--a community that
thrives on the exchange of ideas, expressions of affection, shared memories and humorous
incidents as well as on the material contributions that its members create and support.
The value to others of a person's life is far too precious to allow the individual
to claim a constitutional entitlement to complete autonomy in making a decision to
end that life. Thus, I fully agree with the Court that the "liberty" protected by
the Due Process Clause does not include a categorical "right to commit suicide which
itself includes a right to assistance in doing so." Ante, at 18.
But just as our conclusion that capital punishment is not always unconstitutional
did not preclude later decisions holding that it is sometimes impermissibly cruel,
so is it equally clear that a decision upholding a general statutory prohibition of
assisted suicide does not mean that every possible application of the statute would
be valid. A State, like Washington, that has authorized the death penalty and thereby
has concluded that the sanctity of human life does not require that it always be preserved,
must acknowledge that there are situations in which an interest in hastening death
is legitimate. Indeed, not only is that interest sometimes legitimate, I am also convinced
that there are times when it is entitled to constitutional protection.
In Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dept. of Health, 497 U.S. 261 (1990), the Court assumed
that the interest in liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment encompassed the
right of a terminally ill patient to direct the withdrawal of life sustaining treatment.
As the Courtcorrectly observes today, that assumption "was not simply deduced from
abstract concepts of personal autonomy." Ante, at 21. Instead, it was supported by
the common law tradition protecting the individual's general right to refuse unwanted
medical treatment. Ibid. We have recognized, however, that this common law right to
refuse treatment is neither absolute nor always sufficiently weighty to overcome valid
countervailing state interests. As Justice Brennan pointed out in his Cruzan dissent,
we have upheld legislation imposing punishment on persons refusing to be vaccinated,
497 U.S., at 312 , n. 12, citing Jacobson v. Massachusetts, 197 U.S. 11, 26 -27 (1905),
and as Justice Scalia pointed out in his concurrence, the State ordinarily has the
right to interfere with an attempt to commit suicide by, for example, forcibly placing
a bandage on a self inflicted wound to stop the flow of blood. 497 U.S., at 298 .
In most cases, the individual's constitutionally protected interest in his or her
own physical autonomy, including the right to refuse unwanted medical treatment, will
give way to the State's interest in preserving human life.
Cruzan, however, was not the normal case. Given the irreversible nature of her illness
and the progressive character of her suffering, 9 Nancy Cruzan's interest in refusing
medical care was incidental to her more basic interest in controlling the manner and
timing of her death. In finding that her best interests would be served by cutting
off the nourishment that kept her alive, the trial court did more than simply vindicate
Cruzan's interest in refusing medical treatment; the court, in essence, authorized
affirmative conduct that would hasten her death. When this Court reviewed the case
and upheld Missouri's requirement that there beclear and convincing evidence establishing
Nancy Cruzan's intent to have life sustaining nourishment withdrawn, it made two important
assumptions: (1) that there was a "liberty interest" in refusing unwanted treatment
protected by the Due Process Clause; and (2) that this liberty interest did not "end
the inquiry" because it might be outweighed by relevant state interests. Id., at 279.
I agree with both of those assumptions, but I insist that the source of Nancy Cruzan's
right to refuse treatment was not just a common law rule. Rather, this right is an
aspect of a far broader and more basic concept of freedom that is even older than
the common law. 10 This freedom embraces, not merely a person's right to refuse a
particular kind of unwanted treatment, but also her interest in dignity, and in determining
the character of the memories that will survive long after her death. 11 In recognizing
that the State's interests did not outweigh Nancy Cruzan's liberty interest in refusing
medical treatment, Cruzan rested not simply on the common law right to refuse medical
treatment, but--at least implicitly--on the even more fundamental right to make this
"deeply personal decision," 497 U.S., at 289 (O'Connor, J., concurring).
Thus, the common law right to protection from battery, which included the right to
refuse medical treatment in most circumstances, did not mark "the outer limits of
the substantive sphere of liberty" that supported the Cruzan family's decision to
hasten Nancy's death. Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833,
848 (1992). Those limits have never been precisely defined. They are generally identified
by the importance and character of the decision confronted by the individual, Whalen
v. Roe, 429 U.S. 589, 599 -600, n. 26 (1977). Whatever the outer limits of the concept
may be, it definitely includes protection for matters "central to personal dignity
and autonomy." Casey, 505 U.S., at 851 . It includes,
"the individual's right to make certain unusually important decisions that will affect
his own, or his family's, destiny. The Court has referred to such decisions as implicating
`basic values,' as being `fundamental,' and as being dignified by history and tradition.
The character of the Court's language in these cases brings to mind the origins of
the American heritage of freedom--the abiding interest in individual liberty that
makes certain state intrusions on the citizen's right to decide how he will live his
own life intolerable." Fitzgerald v. Porter Memorial Hospital, 523 F. 2d 716, 719-720
(CA7 1975) (footnotes omitted), cert. denied, 425 U.S. 916 (1976).
The Cruzan case demonstrated that some state intrusions on the right to decide how
death will be encountered are also intolerable. The now deceased plaintiffs in this
action may in fact have had a liberty interest even stronger than Nancy Cruzan's because,
not only were they terminally ill, they were suffering constant and severe pain. Avoiding
intolerable pain and the indignity of living one's final days incapacitated and in
agony is certainly "[a]t the heart of [the] liberty . . . to define one's own concept
of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life." Casey,
505 U.S., at 851 .
While I agree with the Court that Cruzan does not decide the issue presented by these
cases, Cruzan did give recognition, not just to vague, unbridled notions of autonomy,
but to the more specific interest in making decisions about how to confront an imminent
death. Although there is no absolute right to physician assisted suicide, Cruzan makes
it clear that some individuals who no longer have the option of deciding whether to
live or to die because they are already on the threshold of death have a constitutionally
protected interest that may outweigh the State's interest in preserving life at all
costs. The liberty interest at stake in a case like this differs from, and is stronger
than, both the common law right to refuse medical treatment and the unbridled interest
in deciding whether to live or die. It is an interest in deciding how, rather than
whether, a critical threshold shall be crossed.
The state interests supporting a general rule banning the practice of physician assisted
suicide do not have the same force in all cases. First and foremost of these interests
is the " `unqualified interest in the preservation of human life,' " ante, at 24,
(quoting Cruzan, 497 U.S., at 282 ,) which is equated with " `the sanctity of life,'
" ante, at 25, (quoting the American Law Institute, Model Penal Code §210.5, Comment
5, p. 100 (Official Draft and Revised Comments 1980)). That interest not only justifies--it
commands--maximum protection of every individual's interest in remaining alive, which
in turn commands the same protection for decisions about whether to commence or to
terminate life support systems or to administer pain medication that may hasten death.
Properly viewed, however, this interest is not a collective interest that should always
outweigh the interests of a person who because of pain, incapacity, or sedation finds
her life intolerable, but rather, an aspect of individual freedom.
Many terminally ill people find their lives meaningful even if filled with pain or
dependence on others. Some find value in living through suffering; some have an abiding
desire to witness particular events in their families' lives; many believe it a sin
to hasten death. Individuals of different religious faiths make different judgments
and choices about whether to live on under such circumstances. There are those who
will want to continue aggressive treatment; those who would prefer terminal sedation;
and those who will seek withdrawal from life support systems and death by gradual
starvation and dehydration. Although as a general matter the State's interest in the
contributions each person may make to society outweighs the person's interest in ending
her life, this interest does not have the same force for a terminally ill patient
faced not with the choice of whether to live, only of how to die. Allowingthe individual,
rather than the State, to make judgments " `about the "quality" of life that a particular
individual may enjoy.' " ante, at 25 (quoting Cruzan, 497 U.S., at 282 ), does not
mean that the lives of terminally ill, disabled people have less value than the lives
of those who are healthy, see ante, at 28. Rather, it gives proper recognition to
the individual's interest in choosing a final chapter that accords with her life story,
rather than one that demeans her values and poisons memories of her. See Brief for
Bioethicists as Amici Curiae 11; see also R. Dworkin, Life's Dominion 213 (1993) ("Whether
it is in someone's best interests that his life end in one way rather than another
depends on so much else that is special about him--about the shape and character of
his life and his own sense of his integrity and critical interests--that no uniform
collective decision can possibly hope to serve everyone even decently").
Similarly, the State's legitimate interests in preventing suicide, protecting the
vulnerable from coercion and abuse, and preventing euthanasia are less significant
in this context. I agree that the State has a compelling interest in preventing persons
from committing suicide because of depression, or coercion by third parties. But the
State's legitimate interest in preventing abuse does not apply to an individual who
is not victimized by abuse, who is not suffering from depression, and who makes a
rational and voluntary decision to seek assistance in dying. Although, as the New
York Task Force report discusses, diagnosing depression and other mental illness is
not always easy, mental health workers and other professionals expert in working with
dying patients can help patients cope with depression and pain, and help patients
assess their options. See Brief for Washington State Psychological Association et
al. as Amici Curiae 8-10.
Relatedly, the State and amici express the concern that patients whose physical pain
is inadequately treated will be more likely to request assisted suicide. Encouraging
the development and ensuring the availability of adequate pain treatment is of utmost
importance; palliative care, however, cannot alleviate all pain and suffering. See
Orentlicher, Legalization of Physician Assisted Suicide: A Very Modest Revolution,
38 Boston College L. Rev. (Galley, p. 8) (1997) ("Greater use of palliative care would
reduce the demand for assisted suicide, but it will not eliminate [it]"); see also
Brief for Coalition of Hospice Professionals as Amici Curiae 8 (citing studies showing
that "[a]s death becomes more imminent, pain and suffering become progressively more
difficult to treat"). An individual adequately informed of the care alternatives thus
might make a rational choice for assisted suicide. For such an individual, the State's
interest in preventing potential abuse and mistake is only minimally implicated.
The final major interest asserted by the State is its interest in preserving the
traditional integrity of the medical profession. The fear is that a rule permitting
physicians to assist in suicide is inconsistent with the perception that they serve
their patients solely as healers. But for some patients, it would be a physician's
refusal to dispense medication to ease their suffering and make their death tolerable
and dignified that would be inconsistent with the healing role See Block & Billings,
Patient Request to Hasten Death, 154 Archives Internal Med. 2039, 2045 (1994) (A doctor's
refusal to hasten death "may be experienced by the [dying] patient as an abandonment,
a rejection, or an expression of inappropriate paternalistic authority"). For doctors
who have long standing relationships with their patients, who have given their patients
advice on alternative treatments, who are attentive to their patient's individualized
needs, and who are knowledgeable about pain symptom management and palliative care
options, see Quill, Death and Dignity, A Case of Individualized DecisionMaking, 324
New England J. of Med. 691-694 (1991), heeding a patient's desire to assist in her
suicide would not serve to harm the physician patient relationship. Furthermore, because
physicians are already involved in making decisions that hasten the death of terminally
ill patients--through termination of life support, withholding of medical treatment,
and terminal sedation--there is in fact significant tension between the traditional
view of the physician's role and the actual practice in a growing number of cases.
12
As the New York State Task Force on Life and the Law recognized, a State's prohibition
of assisted suicide is justified by the fact that the " `ideal' " case in which "patients
would be screened for depression and offered treatment, effective pain medication
would be available, and all patients would have a supportive committed family and
doctor" is not the usual case. New York State Task Force on Life and the Law, When
Death Is Sought: Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in the Medical Context 120 (May 1994).
Although, as the Court concludes today, these potential harms are sufficient to support
the State's general public policy against assisted suicide, they will not always outweigh
the individual liberty interest of a particular patient. Unlike the Court of Appeals,
I would not say as a categorical matter that these state interests are invalid as
to the entire class of terminally ill, mentally competent patients. I do not, however,
foreclose the possibility that an individual plaintiff seeking to hasten her death,
or a doctor whose assistance was sought, could prevail in a more particularized challenge.
Future cases will determine whether such a challenge may succeed.
In New York, a doctor must respect a competent person's decision to refuse or to
discontinue medical treatment even though death will thereby ensue, but the same doctor
would be guilty of a felony if she provided her patient assistance in committing suicide.
13 Today we hold that the Equal Protection Clause is not violated by the resulting
disparate treatment of two classes of terminally ill people who may have the same
interest in hastening death. I agree that the distinction between permitting death
to ensue from an underlying fatal disease and causing it to occur by the administration
of medication or other means provides a constitutionally sufficient basis for the
State's classification. 14 Unlike the Court, however, see Vacco, ante, at 6-7, I am
not persuaded that in all cases there will in fact be a significant difference between
the intent of the physicians, the patients or the families in the two situations.
There may be little distinction between the intent of a terminally ill patient who
decides to remove her life support and one who seeks the assistance of a doctor in
ending her life; in both situations, the patient is seeking to hasten a certain, impending
death. The doctor's intent might also be the same in prescribing lethal medication
as it is in terminating life support. A doctor who fails to administer medical treatment
to one who is dying from a disease could be doing so with an intent to harm or kill
that patient. Conversely, a doctor who prescribes lethal medication does not necessarily
intend the patient's death--rather that doctor may seek simply to ease the patient's
suffering and to comply with her wishes. The illusory character of any differences
in intent or causation is confirmed by the fact that the American Medical Association
unequivocally endorses the practice of terminal sedation--the administration of sufficient
dosages of pain killing medication to terminally ill patients to protect them from
excruciating pain even when it is clear that the time of death will be advanced. The
purpose of terminal sedation is to ease the suffering of the patient and comply with
her wishes, and the actual cause of death is the administration of heavy doses of
lethal sedatives. This same intent and causation may exist when a doctor complies
with a patient's request for lethal medication to hasten her death. 15
Thus, although the differences the majority notes in causation and intent between
terminating life support and assisting in suicide support the Court's rejection of
the respondents' facial challenge, these distinctions may be inapplicable to particular
terminally ill patients and their doctors. Our holding today in Vacco v. Quill that
the Equal Protection Clause is not violated by New York's classification, just like
our holding in Washington v. Glucksberg that the Washington statute is not invalid
on its face, does not foreclose the possibility that some applications of the New
York statute may impose an intolerable intrusion on the patient's freedom.
There remains room for vigorous debate about the outcome of particular cases that
are not necessarily resolved by the opinions announced today. How such cases may be
decided will depend on their specific facts. In my judgment, however, it is clear
that the so called "unqualified interest in the preservation of human life," Cruzan,
497 U.S., at 282 , Glucksberg, ante, at 24, is not itself sufficient to outweigh the
interest in liberty that may justify the only possible means of preserving a dying
patient's dignity and alleviating her intolerable suffering.
----------------------------------------------------------------------------
U.S. Supreme Court
No. 95-1858
DENNIS C. VACCO, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF NEW YORK, et al., PETITIONERS v. TIMOTHY E.
QUILL et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 26, 1997]
Justice Souter, concurring in the judgment.
Even though I do not conclude that assisted suicide is a fundamental right entitled
to recognition at this time, I accord the claims raised by the patients and physicians
in this case and Washington v. Glucksberg a high degree of importance, requiring a
commensurate justification. See Washington v. Glucksberg, ante, at 24-41 (Souter,
J., concurring in judgment). The reasons that lead me to conclude in Glucksberg that
the prohibition on assisted suicide is not arbitrary under the due process standard
also support the distinction between assistance to suicide, which is banned, and practices
such as termination of artificial life support and death hastening pain medication,
which are permitted. I accordingly concur in the judgment of the Court.
Footnotes
[ Footnote 1 ] N. Y. Penal Law §125.15 (McKinney 1987) ("Manslaughter in the second
degree") provides: "A person is guilty of manslaughter in the second degree when .
. . (3) He intentionally causes or aids another person to commit suicide. Manslaughter
in the second degree is a class C felony." Section 120.30 ("Promoting a suicide attempt")
states: "A person is guilty of promoting a suicide attempt when he intentionally causes
or aids another person to attempt suicide. Promoting a suicide attempt is a class
E felony." See generally, Washington v. Glucksberg, ___ U. S. ___ (1997), ante, at
4-15.
[ Footnote 2 ] %It is established under New York law that a competent person may
refuse medical treatment, even if the withdrawal of such treatment will result in
death." Quill v. Koppell, 870 F. Supp. 78, 84 (SDNY 1994); see N. Y. Pub. Health Law,
Art. 29-B, §§2960-2979 (McKinney 1993 & Supp. 1997) ("Orders Not to Resuscitate")
(regulating right of "adult with capacity" to direct issuance of orders not to resuscitate);
id., §§2980-2994 ("Health Care Agents and Proxies") (allowing appointment of agents
"to make . . . health care decisions on the principal's behalf," including decisions
to refuse lifesaving treatment).
[ Footnote 3 ] Declaration of Timothy E. Quill, M. D., App. 42-49; Declaration of
Samuel C. Klagsbrun, M. D., id., at 68-74; Declaration of Howard A. Grossman, M. D.,
id., at 84-89; 80 F. 3d 716, 719 (CA2 1996).
[ Footnote 4 ] These three patients stated that they had no chance of recovery, faced
the "prospect of progressive loss of bodily function and integrity and increasing
pain and suffering," and desired medical assistance in ending their lives. App. 25-26;
Declaration of William A. Barth, id., at 96-98; Declaration of George A. Kingsley,
id., at 99-102; Declaration of Jane Doe, id., at 105-109.
[ Footnote 5 ] The court acknowledged that because New York's assisted suicide statutes
"do not impinge on any fundamental rights [or] involve suspect classifications," they
were subject only to rational basis judicial scrutiny. 80 F. 3d, at 726-727.
[ Footnote 6 ] The American Medical Association emphasizes the "fundamental difference
between refusing life sustaining treatment and demanding a life ending treatment."
American Medical Association, Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, Physician Assisted
Suicide, 10 Issues in Law & Medicine 91, 93 (1994); see also American Medical Association,
Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, Decisions Near the End of Life, 267 JAMA
2229, 2230-2231, 2233 (1992) ("The withdrawing or withholding of life sustaining treatment
is not inherently contrary to the principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence," but
assisted suicide "is contrary to the prohibition against using the tools of medicine
to cause a patient's death"); New York State Task Force on Life and the Law, When
Death is Sought: Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in the Medical Context 108 (1994)
("[Professional organizations] consistently distinguish assisted suicide and euthanasia
from the withdrawing or withholding of treatment, and from the provision of palliative
treatments or other medical care that risk fatal side effects"); Brief for the American
Medical Association et al. as Amici Curiae 18-25. Of course, as respondents' lawsuit
demonstrates, there are differences of opinion within the medical profession on this
question. See New York Task Force, When Death is Sought, supra, at 104-109.
[ Footnote 7 ] Thus, the Second Circuit erred in reading New York law as creating
a "right to hasten death"; instead, the authorities cited by the court recognize a
right to refuse treatment, and nowhere equate the exercise of this right with suicide.
Schloendorff v. Society of New York Hospital, 211 N. Y. 125, 129-130, 105 N. E. 92,
93 (1914), which contains Justice Cardozo's famous statement that "[e]very human being
of adult years and sound mind has a right to determine what shall be done with his
own body," was simply an informed consent case. See also Rivers v. Katz, 67 N. Y.
2d 485, 495, 495 N. E. 2d 337, 343 (1986) (right to refuse anti-psychotic medication
is not absolute, and may be limited when "the patient presents a danger to himself");
Matter of Storar, 52 N. Y. 2d 363, 377, n. 6, 420 N. E. 2d 64, 71, n. 6, cert. denied,
454 U.S. 858 (1981).
[ Footnote 8 ] Many courts have recognized this distinction. See, e.g., Kevorkian
v.Thompson, 947 F. Supp. 1152, 1178, and nn. 20-21 (ED Mich. 1997); In re Fiori, 543
Pa. 592, 602, 673 A. 2d 905, 910 (1996); Singletary v. Costello, 665 So. 2d 1099,
1106 (Fla. App. 1996); Laurie v. Senecal, 666 A. 2d 806, 808-809 (R. I. 1995); State
ex rel. Schuetzle v. Vogel, 537 N. W. 2d 358, 360 (N. D. 1995); Thor v. Superior Court,
5 Cal. 4th 725, 741-742, 855 P. 2d 375, 385-386 (1993); DeGrella v. Elston, 858 S.
W. 2d 698, 707 (Ky. 1993); People v. Adams, 216 Cal. App. 3d 1431, 1440, 265 Cal.
Rptr. 568, 573-574 (1990); Guardianship of Jane Doe, 411 Mass. 512, 522-523, 583 N.
E. 2d 1263, 1270, cert. denied sub nom. Doe v. Gross, 503 U.S. 950 (1992); In re L.
W., 167 Wis. 2d 53, 83, 482 N. W. 2d 60, 71 (1992); In re Rosebush, 195 Mich. App.
675, 681, n. 2, 491 N. W. 2d 633, 636, n. 2 (1992); Donaldson v. Van de Kamp, 2 Cal.
App. 4th 1614, 1619-1625, 4 Cal. Rptr. 2d 59, 61-64 (1992); In re Lawrance, 579 N.
E. 2d 32, 40, n. 4 (Ind. 1991); McKay v. Bergstedt, 106 Nev. 808, 822-823, 801 P.
2d 617, 626-627 (1990); In re Browning, 568 So. 2d 4, 14 (Fla. 1990); McConnell v.
Beverly Enterprises Connecticut, Inc., 209 Conn. 692, 710, 553 A. 2d 596, 605 (1989);
State v. McAfee, 259 Ga. 579, 581, 385 S. E. 2d 651, 652 (1989); In re Grant, 109
Wash. 2d 545, 563, 747 P. 2d 445, 454-455 (1987); In re Gardner, 534 A. 2d 947, 955-956
(Me. 1987); Matter of Farrell, 108 N. J. 335, 349-350, 529 A. 2d 404, 411 (1987);
Rasmussen v. Fleming, 154 Ariz. 207, 218, 741 P. 2d 674, 685 (1987); Bouvia v. Superior
Court, 179 Cal. App. 3d 1127, 1144-1145, 225 Cal. Rptr. 297, 306 (1986); Von Holden
v. Chapman, 87 App. Div. 2d 66, 70, 450 N. Y. S. 2d 623, 627 (1982); Bartling v. Superior
Court, 163 Cal. App. 3d 186, 196-197, 209 Cal. Rptr. 220, 225-226 (1984); Foody v.
Manchester Memorial Hospital, 40 Conn. Sup. 127, 137, 482 A. 2d 713, 720 (1984); In
re P. V. W., 424 So. 2d 1015, 1022 (La. 1982); Leach v. Akron General Medical Center,
68 Ohio Misc. 1, 10, 426 N. E. 2d 809, 815 (Ohio Comm. Pleas 1980); In re Severns,
425 A. 2d 156, 161 (Del. Ch. 1980); Satz v. Perlmutter, 362 So. 2d 160, 162-163 (Fla.
App. 1978); Application of the President and Directors of Georgetown College, 331
F. 2d 1000, 1009 (CADC), cert. denied, 377 U.S. 978 (1964); Brophy v. New England
Sinai Hospital, 398 Mass. 417, 439, 497 N. E. 2d 626, 638 (1986). The British House
of Lords has also recognized the distinction. Airedale N. H. S. Trust v. Bland, 2
W. L. R. 316, 368 (1993).
[ Footnote 9 ] See Ala. Code §22-8A--10 (1990); Alaska Stat. Ann. §§18.12.080(a),
(f) (1996); Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. §36-3210 (Supp. 1996); Ark. Code Ann. §§20-13-905(a),
(f), 20-17-210(a),(g) (1991 and Supp. 1995); Cal. Health & Safety Code Ann. §§7191.5(a),
(g) (West Supp. 1997); Cal. Prob. Code Ann. §4723 (West. Supp. 1997); Colo. Rev. Stat.
§§15-14-504(4), 15-18-112(1), 15-18.5-101(3), 15-18.6-108 (1987 and Supp. 1996); Conn.
Gen. Stat. §19a--575 (Supp. 1996); Del. Code Ann., Tit. 16, §2512 (Supp. 1996); D.
C. Code Ann. §§6-2430, 21-2212 (1995 and Supp. 1996); Fla. Stat. §§765.309(1), (2)
(Supp. 1997); Ga. Code Ann. §§31-32-11(b), 31-36-2(b) (1996); Haw. Rev. Stat. §327D--13
(1996); Idaho Code §39-152 (Supp. 1996); Ill. Comp. Stat., ch. 755, §§35/9(f), 40/5,
40/50, 45/2-1 (1992); Ind. Code §§16-36-1-13, 16-36-4-19, 30-5-5-17 (1994 and Supp.
1996); Iowa Code §§144A.11.1-144A.11.6, 144B.12.2 (1989 and West Supp. 1997); Kan.
Stat. Ann. §65-28,109 (1985); Ky. Rev. Stat. Ann. §311.638 (Baldwin Supp. 1992); La.
Rev. Stat. Ann. 40: §§1299.58.10(A), (B) (West 1992); Me. Rev. Stat. Ann., Tit. 18-A,
§§5-813(b), (c) (West Supp. 1996); Mass. Gen. Laws 201D, §12 (Supp. 1997); Md. Health
Code Ann. §5-611(c) (1994); Mich. Comp. Laws Ann. §700.496(20) (West 1995); Minn.
Stat. §§145B.14, 145C.14 (Supp. 1997); Miss. Code Ann. §§41-41-117(2),41-41-119(1)
(Supp. 1992); Mo. Rev. Stat. §§459.015.3, 459.055(5) (1992); Mont. Code Ann. §§50-9-205(1),
(7), 50-10-104(1), (6) (1995); Neb. Rev. Stat. §§20-412(1), (7), 30-3401(3) (1995);
N. H. Rev. Stat. Ann. §§137-H:10, 137-H:13, 137 J:1 (1996); N. J. Stat. Ann. §§26:2H--54(d),
(e), 26:2H--77 (West 1996); N. M. Stat. Ann. §§24-7A--13(B)(1), (C) (Supp. 1995);
N. Y. Pub. Health Law §2989(3) (1993); Nev. Rev. Stat. §449.670(2) (1996); N. C. Gen.
Stat. §§90-320(b), 90-321(f) (1993); N. D. Cent. Code §§23-06.4-01, 23-06.5-01 (1991);
Ohio Rev. Code Ann. §2133.12(A), (D) (Supp. 1996); Okla. Stat. Ann., Tit. 63, §§3101.2(C),3101.12(A),(G)
(1996); 20 Pa. Cons. Stat. §5402(b) (Supp. 1996); R. I. Gen. Laws §§23-4.10-9(a),
(f), 23-4.11-10(a), (f) (1996); S. C. Code Ann. §§44-77-130, 44-78-50(A), (C), 62-5-504(O)
(Supp. 1996); S. D. Codified Laws §§34-12D--14, 34-12D--20 (1994); Tenn. Code Ann.
§§32-11-110(a), 39-13-216 (Supp. 1996); Tex. Health & Safety Code Ann. §§672.017,
672.020, 672.021 (1992); Utah Code Ann. §§75-2-1116,75-2-1118 (1993); Va. Code Ann.
§54.1-2990 (1994); Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 18, §5260 (1987); V. I. Code Ann.,Tit. 19,
§§198(a), (g) (1995); Wash. Rev. Code §§70.122.070(1), 70.122.100 (Supp. 1997); W.
Va. Code §§16-30-10, 16-30A--16(a), 16-30B--2(b), 16-30B--13, 16-30C--14 (1995); Wis.
Stat. §§154.11(1), (6), 154.25(7), 155.70(7) (Supp. 1996); Wyo. Stat. §§3-5-211, 35-22-109,
35-22-208 (1994 & Supp. 1996). See also, 42 U.S.C. § 14402(b)(1), (2), (4) ("Assisted
Suicide Funding Restriction Act of 1997").
[ Footnote 10 ] It has always been a crime, either by statute or under the common
law, to assist a suicide in New York. See Marzen, O'Dowd, Crone, & Balch, Suicide:
A Constitutional Right?, 24 Duquesne L. Rev. 1, 205-210 (1985) (Appendix).
[ Footnote 11 ] Respondents also argue that the State irrationally distinguishes
between physician assisted suicide and "terminal sedation," a process respondents
characterize as "induc[ing] barbiturate coma and then starv[ing] the person to death."
Brief for Respondents 48-50; see 80 F. 3d, at 729. Petitioners insist, however, that
" `[a]lthough proponents of physician assisted suicide and euthanasia contend that
terminal sedation is covert physician assisted suicide or euthanasia, the concept
of sedating pharmacotherapy is based on informed consent and the principle of double
effect.' " Reply Brief for Petitioners 12 (quoting P. Rousseau, Terminal Sedation
in the Care of Dying Patients, 156 Archives Internal Med. 1785, 1785-1786 (1996)).
Just as a State may prohibit assisting suicide while permitting patients to refuse
unwanted lifesaving treatment, it may permit palliative care related to that refusal,
which may have the foreseen but unintended "double effect" of hastening the patient's
death. See New York Task Force, When Death is Sought, supra, n. 6, at 163 ("It is
widely recognized that the provision of pain medication is ethically and professionally
acceptable even when the treatment may hasten the patient's death, if the medication
is intended to alleviate pain and severe discomfort, not to cause death").
[ Footnote 12 ] We do not insist, as Justice Stevens suggests, ante, at 14-15 (concurring
opinion), that "in all cases there will in fact be a significant difference between
the intent of the physicians, the patients or the families [in withdrawal of treatment
and physician assisted suicide cases]." See 6-7, supra ("[A] physician who withdraws,
or honors a patient's refusal to begin, life sustaining medical treatment purposefully
intends, or may so intend, only to respect his patient's wishes . . . . The same is
true when a doctor provides aggressive palliative care; . . . the physician's purpose
and intent is, or may be, only to ease his patient's pain") (emphasis added). In the
absence of omniscience, however, the State is entitled to act on the reasonableness
of the distinction.
[ Footnote 13 ] Justice Stevens observes that our holding today "does not foreclose
the possibility that some applications of the New York statute may impose an intolerable
intrusion on the patient's freedom." Ante, at 16 (concurring opinion). This is true,
but, as we observe in Glucksberg, ante, at 31-32, n. 24, a particular plaintiff hoping
to show that New York's assisted suicide ban was unconstitutional in his particular
case would need to present different and considerably stronger arguments than those
advanced by respondents here.
[ Footnote * ] Justice Ginsburg concurs in the Court's judgments substantially for
the reasons stated in this opinion. Justice Breyer joins this opinion except insofar
as it joins the opinions of the Court.
[ Footnote 1 ] Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976)
[ Footnote 2 ] Proffitt v. Florida, 428 U.S. 242 (1976).
[ Footnote 3 ] Jurek v. Texas, 428 U.S. 262 (1976).
[ Footnote 4 ] See, e.g., Godfrey v. Georgia, 446 U.S. 420 (1980); Enmund v. Florida,
458 U.S. 782 (1982); Penry v. Lynaugh, 492 U.S. 302 (1989).
[ Footnote 5 ] See ante, at 3, n. 5.
[ Footnote 6 ] If the Court had actually applied the Salerno standard in this action,
it would have taken only a few paragraphs to identify situations in which the Washington
statute could be validly enforced. In Salerno itself, the Court would have needed
only to look at whether the statute could be constitutionally applied to the arrestees
before it; any further analysis would have been superfluous. See Dorf, Facial Challenges
to State and Federal Statutes, 46 Stan. L. Rev. 235, 239-240 (1994) (arguing that
if the Salerno standard were taken literally, a litigant could not succeed in her
facial challenge unless she also succeeded in her as applied challenge).
[ Footnote 7 ] In other cases and in other contexts, we have imposed a significantly
lesser burden on the challenger. The most lenient standard that we have applied requires
the challenger to establish that the invalid applications of a statute "must not only
be real, but substantial as well, judged in relation to the statute's plainly legitimate
sweep." Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U.S. 601, 615 (1973). As the Court's opinion demonstrates,
Washington's statute prohibiting assisted suicide has a "plainly legitimate sweep."
While that demonstration provides a sufficient justification for rejecting respondents'
facial challenge, it does not mean that every application of the statute should or
will be upheld.
[ Footnote 8 ] "Who casts not up his eye to the sun when it rises? but who takes
off his eye from a comet when that breaks out? Who bends not his ear to any bell which
upon any occasion rings? but who can remove it from that bell which is passing a piece
of himself out of this world? No man is an island, entire of itself; every man is
a piece of the continent, a part of the main. If a clod be washed away by the sea,
Europe is the less, as well as if a promontory were, as well as if a manor of thy
friend's or of thine own were; any man's death diminishes me, because I am involved
in mankind; and therefore never send to know for whom the belltolls; it tolls for
thee." J. Donne, Meditation No. 17, Devotions Upon Emergent Occasions 86, 87 (A. Raspa
ed. 1987).
[ Footnote 9 ] See 497 U.S., at 332 , n. 2.
[ Footnote 10 ] "[N]either the Bill of Rights nor the laws of sovereign States create
the liberty which the Due Process Clause protects. The relevant constitutional provisions
are limitations on the power of the sovereign to infringe on the liberty of the citizen.
The relevant state laws either create property rights, or they curtail the freedom
of the citizen who must live in an ordered society. Of course, law is essential to
the exercise and enjoyment of individual liberty in a complex society. But it is not
the source of liberty, and surely not the exclusive source. "I had thought it self
evident that all men were endowed by their Creator with liberty as one of the cardinal
unalienable rights. It is that basic freedom which the Due Process Clause protects,
rather than the particular rights or privileges conferred by specific laws or regulations."
Meachum v. Fano, 427 U.S. 215, 230 (1976) (Stevens, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 11 ] "Nancy Cruzan's interest in life, no less than that of any other
person, includes an interest in how she will be thought of after her death by those
whose opinions mattered to her. There can be no doubt that her life made her dear
to her family and to others. How she dies will affect how that life is remembered."
Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dept. of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 344 (1990) (Stevens, J., dissenting).
"Each of us has an interest in the kind of memories that will survive after death.
To that end, individual decisions are often motivated by their impact on others. A
member of the kind of family identified in the trial court's findings in this case
would likely have not only a normal interest in minimizing the burden that her own
illness imposes on others, but also an interest in having their memories of her filled
predominantly with thoughts about her past vitality rather than her current condition."
Id., at 356.
[ Footnote 12 ] I note that there is evidence that a significant number of physicians
support the practice of hastening death in particular situations. A survey published
in the New England Journal of Medicine, found that 56% of responding doctors in Michigan
preferred legalizing assisted suicide to an explicit ban. Bachman et al., Attitudes
of Michigan Physicians and the Public Toward Legalizing Physician Assisted Suicide
and Voluntary Euthanasia, 334 New England J. Med. 303-309 (1996). In a survey of Oregon
doctors, 60% of the responding doctors supported legalizing assisted suicide for terminally
ill patients. See Lee et al., Legalizing Assisted Suicide--Views of Physicians in
Oregon, 335 New England J. Med. 310-315 (1996). Another study showed that 12% of physicians
polled in Washington State reported that they had been asked by their terminally ill
patients for prescriptions to hasten death, and that, in the year prior to the study,
24% of those physicians had complied with such requests. See Back, Wallace, Starks,
& Perlman, Physician Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in Washington State, 275 JAMA
919-925 (1996); see also Doukas, Waterhouse, Gorenflo, & Seld, Attitudes and Behaviors
on Physician Assisted Death: A Study of Michigan Oncologists, 13 J. Clinical Oncology
1055 (1995) (reporting that 18% of responding Michigan oncologists reported active
participation in assisted suicide); Slome, Moulton, Huffine, Gorter, & Abrams, Physicians'
Attitudes Toward Assisted Suicide in AIDS, 5 J. Acquired Immune Deficiency Syndromes
712 (1992) (reporting that 24% of responding physicians who treat AIDS patients would
likely grant a patient's request for assistance in hastening death).
[ Footnote 13 ] See Vacco v. Quill, ante, at 1, nn. 1 and 2.
[ Footnote 14 ] The American Medical Association recognized this distinction when
it supported Nancy Cruzan and continues to recognize this distinction in its support
of the States in these cases.
[ Footnote 15 ] If a doctor prescribes lethal drugs to be self administered by the
patient, it not at all clear that the physician's intent is that the patient "be made
dead," ante, at 7 (internal quotation marks omitted). Many patients prescribed lethal
medications never actually take them; they merely acquire some sense of control in
the process of dying that the availability of those medications provides. See Back,
supra n. 12, at 922; see also Quill, 324 New England J. Med., at 693 (describing how
some patients fear death less when they feel they have the option of physician assisted
suicide).