Constitutional Law Cases: Rehnquist Court
1990 - 1999
U.S. Supreme Court
ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996)
ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996)
ROY ROMER, GOVERNOR OF COLORADO, ET AL. PETITIONERS v. RICHARD G. EVANS ET AL.
CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF COLORADO
No. 94-1039
Argued October 10, 1995
Decided May 20, 1996
After various Colorado municipalities passed ordinances banning discrimination based
on sexual orientation in housing, employment, education, public accommodations, health
and welfare services, and other transactions and activities, Colorado voters adopted
by statewide referendum "Amendment 2" to the State Constitution, which precludes all
legislative, executive, or judicial action at any level of state or local government
designed to protect the status of persons based on their "homosexual, lesbian or bisexual
orientation, conduct, practices or relationships." Respondents, who include aggrieved
homosexuals and municipalities, commenced this litigation in state court against petitioner
state parties to declare Amendment 2 invalid and enjoin its enforcement. The trial
court's grant of a preliminary injunction was sustained by the Colorado Supreme Court,
which held that Amendment 2 was subject to strict scrutiny under the Equal Protection
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment because it infringed the fundamental right of gays
and lesbians to participate in the political process. On remand, the trial court found
that the Amendment failed to satisfy strict scrutiny. It enjoined Amendment 2's enforcement,
and the State Supreme Court affirmed.
Held:
Amendment 2 violates the Equal Protection Clause. Pp. 4-14.
(a) The State's principal argument that Amendment 2 puts gays and lesbians in the
same position as all other persons by denying them special rights is rejected as implausible.
The extent of the change in legal status effected by this law is evident from the
authoritative construction of Colorado's Supreme Court - which establishes that the
amendment's immediate effect is to repeal all existing statutes, regulations, ordinances,
and policies of state and local entities barring discrimination based on sexual orientation,
and that its ultimate effect is to prohibit any governmental entity from adopting
similar, or more protective, measures in the future absent state constitutional amendment
- and from a review of the terms, structure, Page II and operation of the ordinances
that would be repealsed and prohibited by Amendment 2. Even if, as the State contends,
homosexuals can find protection in laws and policies of general application, Amendment
2 goes well beyond merely depriving them of special rights. It imposes a broad disability
upon those persons alone, forbidding them, but no others, to seek specific legal protection
from injuries caused by discrimination in a wide range of public and private transactions.
Pp. 4-9.
(b) In order to reconcile the Fourteenth Amendment's promise that no person shall
be denied equal protection with the practical reality that most legislation classifies
for one purpose or another, the Court has stated that it will uphold a law that neither
burdens a fundamental right nor targets a suspect class so long as the legislative
classification bears a rational relation to some independent and legitimate legislative
end. See, e.g., Heller v. Doe, 509 U.S. 312, 319 -320. Amendment 2 fails, indeed defies,
even this conventional inquiry. First, the amendment is at once too narrow and too
broad, identifying persons by a single trait and then denying them the possibility
of protection across the board. This disqualification of a class of persons from the
right to obtain specific protection from the law is unprecedented and is itself a
denial of equal protection in the most literal sense. Second, the sheer breadth of
Amendment 2, which makes a general announcement that gays and lesbians shall not have
any particular protections from the law, is so far removed from the reasons offered
for it, i.e., respect for other citizens' freedom of association, particularly landlords
or employers who have personal or religious objections to homosexuality, and the State's
interest in conserving resources to fight discrimination against other groups, that
the amendment cannot be explained by reference to those reasons; the Amendment raises
the inevitable inference that it is born of animosity toward the class that it affects.
Amendment 2 cannot be said to be directed to an identifiable legitimate purpose or
discrete objective. It is a status-based classification of persons undertaken for
its own sake, something the Equal Protection Clause does not permit. Pp. 9-14.
882 P.2d 1335, affirmed.
KENNEDY, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which STEVENS, O'CONNOR, SOUTER,
GINSBURG, and BREYER, JJ., joined. SCALIA, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which
REHNQUIST, C. J., and THOMAS, J., joined. [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) ,
1]
JUSTICE KENNEDY delivered the opinion of the Court.
One century ago, the first Justice Harlan admonished this Court that the Constitution
"neither knows nor tolerates classes among citizens." Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S.
537, 559 (1896) (dissenting opinion). Unheeded then, those words now are understood
to state a commitment to the law's neutrality where the rights of persons are at stake.
The Equal Protection Clause enforces this principle and today requires us to hold
invalid a provision of Colorado's Constitution.
I
The enactment challenged in this case is an amendment to the Constitution of the
State of Colorado, adopted in a 1992 statewide referendum. The parties and the state
courts refer to it as "Amendment 2," its designation when submitted to the voters.
The impetus for the amendment and the contentious campaign that preceded its adoption
came in large part from ordinances that had been passed in various Colorado municipalities.
For example, the cities of Aspen and Boulder and the City and County of Denver each
had enacted ordinances which banned discrimination in many transactions and activities,
including housing, employment, education, public accommodations, and health and welfare
services. Denver Rev. Municipal Code, Art. IV 28-91 to 28-116 (1991); Aspen Municipal
Code 13-98 (1977); Boulder Rev. Code 12-1-1 [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996)
, 2] to 12-1-11 (1987). What gave rise to the statewide controversy was the protection
the ordinances afforded to persons discriminated against by reason of their sexual
orientation. See Boulder Rev. Code 12-1-1 (defining "sexual orientation" as "the choice
of sexual partners, i.e., bisexual, homosexual or heterosexual"); Denver Rev. Municipal
Code, Art. IV 28-92 (defining "sexual orientation" as "[t]he status of an individual
as to his or her heterosexuality, homosexuality or bisexuality"). Amendment 2 repeals
these ordinances to the extent they prohibit discrimination on the basis of "homosexual,
lesbian or bisexual orientation, conduct, practices or relationships." Colo. Const.,
Art. II, 30b.
Yet Amendment 2, in explicit terms, does more than repeal or rescind these provisions.
It prohibits all legislative, executive or judicial action at any level of state or
local government designed to protect the named class, a class we shall refer to as
homosexual persons or gays and lesbians. The amendment reads:
"No Protected Status Based on Homosexual, Lesbian, or Bisexual Orientation. Neither
the State of Colorado, through any of its branches or departments, nor any of its
agencies, political subdivisions, municipalities or school districts, shall enact,
adopt or enforce any statute, regulation, ordinance or policy whereby homosexual,
lesbian or bisexual orientation, conduct, practices or relationships shall constitute
or otherwise be the basis of or entitle any person or class of persons to have or
claim any minority status, quota preferences, protected status or claim of discrimination.
This Section of the Constitution shall be in all respects self-executing." Ibid.
Soon after Amendment 2 was adopted, this litigation to declare its invalidity and
enjoin its enforcement was commenced in the District Court for the City and County
of Denver. Among the plaintiffs (respondents here) were homosexual persons, some of
them government employees. They alleged that enforcement of Amendment 2 would subject
[ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 3] them to immediate and substantial risk
of discrimination on the basis of their sexual orientation. Other plaintiffs (also
respondents here) included the three municipalities whose ordinances we have cited
and certain other governmental entities which had acted earlier to protect homosexuals
from discrimination but would be prevented by Amendment 2 from continuing to do so.
Although Governor Romer had been on record opposing the adoption of Amendment 2, he
was named in his official capacity as a defendant, together with the Colorado Attorney
General and the State of Colorado.
The trial court granted a preliminary injunction to stay enforcement of Amendment
2, and an appeal was taken to the Supreme Court of Colorado. Sustaining the interim
injunction and remanding the case for further proceedings, the State Supreme Court
held that Amendment 2 was subject to strict scrutiny under the Fourteenth Amendment
because it infringed the fundamental right of gays and lesbians to participate in
the political process. Evans v. Romer, 854 P.2d 1270 (Colo. 1993) (Evans I). To reach
this conclusion, the state court relied on our voting rights cases, e.g., Reynolds
v. Sims, 377 U.S. 533 (1964); Carrington v. Rash, 380 U.S. 89 (1965); Harper v. Virginia
Bd. of Elections, 383 U.S. 663 (1966); Williams v. Rhodes, 393 U.S. 23 (1968), and
on our precedents involving discriminatory restructuring of governmental decisionmaking,
see, e.g., Hunter v. Erickson, 393 U.S. 385 (1969); Reitman v. Mulkey, 387 U.S. 369
(1967); Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 458 U.S. 457 (1982); Gordon v. Lance,
403 U.S. 1 (1971). On remand, the State advanced various arguments in an effort to
show that Amendment 2 was narrowly tailored to serve compelling interests, but the
trial court found none sufficient. It enjoined enforcement of Amendment 2, and the
Supreme Court of Colorado, in a second opinion, affirmed the ruling. Evans v. Romer,
882 P.2d 1335 (Colo. 1994) (Evans II). We granted certiorari and now affirm the judgment,
but on a rationale different from that adopted by the State Supreme Court. [ ROMER
v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 4]
II
The State's principal argument in defense of Amendment 2 is that it puts gays and
lesbians in the same position as all other persons. So, the State says, the measure
does no more than deny homosexuals special rights. This reading of the amendment's
language is implausible. We rely not upon our own interpretation of the amendment
but upon the authoritative construction of Colorado's Supreme Court. The state court,
deeming it unnecessary to determine the full extent of the amendment's reach, found
it invalid even on a modest reading of its implications. The critical discussion of
the amendment, set out in Evans I, is as follows:
"The immediate objective of Amendment 2 is, at a minimum, to repeal existing statutes,
regulations, ordinances, and policies of state and local entities that barred discrimination
based on sexual orientation. See Aspen, Colo., Mun. Code 13-98 (1977) (prohibiting
discrimination in employment, housing and public accommodations on the basis of sexual
orientation); Boulder, Colo., Rev. Code 12-1-2 to -4 (1987) (same); Denver, Colo.,
Rev. Mun. Code art. IV, 28-91 to -116 (1991) (same); Executive Order No. D0035 (December
10, 1990) (prohibiting employment discrimination for `all state employees, classified
and exempt' on the basis of sexual orientation); Colorado Insurance Code, 10-3-1104,
4A C. R. S. (1992 Supp.) (forbidding health insurance providers from determining insurability
and premiums based on an applicant's, a beneficiary's, or an insured's sexual orientation);
and various provisions prohibiting discrimination based on sexual orientation at state
colleges.26.
"26. Metropolitan State College of Denver prohibits college sponsored social clubs
from discriminating in membership on the basis of sexual orientation and Colorado
State University has an antidiscrimination policy which encompasses sexual orientation.
"The `ultimate effect' of Amendment 2 is to prohibit any governmental entity from
adopting similar, or more [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 5] protective statutes,
regulations, ordinances, or policies in the future unless the state constitution is
first amended to permit such measures." 854 P.2d, at 1284-1285, and n. 26.
Sweeping and comprehensive is the change in legal status effected by this law. So
much is evident from the ordinances that the Colorado Supreme Court declared would
be void by operation of Amendment 2. Homosexuals, by state decree, are put in a solitary
class with respect to transactions and relations in both the private and governmental
spheres. The amendment withdraws from homosexuals, but no others, specific legal protection
from the injuries caused by discrimination, and it forbids reinstatement of these
laws and policies.
The change that Amendment 2 works in the legal status of gays and lesbians in the
private sphere is far-reaching, both on its own terms and when considered in light
of the structure and operation of modern anti-discrimination laws. That structure
is well illustrated by contemporary statutes and ordinances prohibiting discrimination
by providers of public accommodations. "At common law, innkeepers, smiths, and others
who `made profession of a public employment,' were prohibited from refusing, without
good reason, to serve a customer." Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual
Group of Boston, Inc., 515 U.S. ___, ___ (1995) (slip op., at 13). The duty was a
general one and did not specify protection for particular groups. The common law rules,
however, proved insufficient in many instances, and it was settled early that the
Fourteenth Amendment did not give Congress a general power to prohibit discrimination
in public accommodations, Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S. 3, 25 (1883). In consequence,
most States have chosen to counter discrimination by enacting detailed statutory schemes.
See, e.g., S. D. Codified Laws 20-13-10, 20-13-22, 20-13-23 (1995); Iowa Code 216.6-216.8
(1994); Okla. Stat., Tit. 25, 1302, 1402 (1987); 43 Pa. Cons. Stat. 953, 955 (Supp.
1995); N. J. Stat. Ann. 10:5-3, 10:5-4 (West Supp. 1995); [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S.
___ (1996) , 6] N. H. Rev. Stat. Ann. 354-A:7, 354-A:10, 354-A:17 (1995); Minn. Stat.
363.03 (1991 and Supp. 1995).
Colorado's state and municipal laws typify this emerging tradition of statutory protection
and follow a consistent pattern. The laws first enumerate the persons or entities
subject to a duty not to discriminate. The list goes well beyond the entities covered
by the common law. The Boulder ordinance, for example, has a comprehensive definition
of entities deemed places of "public accommodation." They include "any place of business
engaged in any sales to the general public and any place that offers services, facilities,
privileges, or advantages to the general public or that receives financial support
through solicitation of the general public or through governmental subsidy of any
kind." Boulder Rev. Code 12-1-1(j) (1987). The Denver ordinance is of similar breadth,
applying, for example, to hotels, restaurants, hospitals, dental clinics, theaters,
banks, common carriers, travel and insurance agencies, and "shops and stores dealing
with goods or services of any kind," Denver Rev. Municipal Code, Art. IV, 28-92.
These statutes and ordinances also depart from the common law by enumerating the
groups or persons within their ambit of protection. Enumeration is the essential device
used to make the duty not to discriminate concrete and to provide guidance for those
who must comply. In following this approach, Colorado's state and local governments
have not limited anti-discrimination laws to groups that have so far been given the
protection of heightened equal protection scrutiny under our cases. See, e.g., J.
E. B. v. Alabama ex rel. T. B., 511 U.S. __, __ (1994) (slip op., at 8) (sex); Lalli
v. Lalli, 439 U.S. 259, 265 (1978) (illegitimacy); McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.S.
184, 191 -192 (1964) (race); Oyama v. California, 332 U.S. 633 (1948) (ancestry).
Rather, they set forth an extensive catalogue of traits which cannot be the basis
for discrimination, including age, military status, marital status, pregnancy, parenthood,
custody of a minor child, political affiliation, physical or mental disability [ ROMER
v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 7] of an individual or of his or her associates -
and, in recent times, sexual orientation. Aspen Municipal Code 13-98(a)(1) (1977);
Boulder Rev. Code 12-1-1 to 12-1-4 (1987); Denver Rev. Municipal Code, Art. IV, 28-92
to 28-119 (1991); Colo. Rev. Stat. 24-34-401 to 24-34-707 (1988 and Supp. 1995).
Amendment 2 bars homosexuals from securing protection against the injuries that these
public-accommodations laws address. That in itself is a severe consequence, but there
is more. Amendment 2, in addition, nullifies specific legal protections for this targeted
class in all transactions in housing, sale of real estate, insurance, health and welfare
services, private education, and employment. See, e.g., Aspen Municipal Code 13-98(b),
(c) (1977); Boulder Rev. Code 12-1-2, 12-1-3 (1987); Denver Rev. Municipal Code, Art.
IV 28-93 to 28-95, 28-97 (1991).
Not confined to the private sphere, Amendment 2 also operates to repeal and forbid
all laws or policies providing specific protection for gays or lesbians from discrimination
by every level of Colorado government. The State Supreme Court cited two examples
of protections in the governmental sphere that are now rescinded and may not be reintroduced.
The first is Colorado Executive Order D0035 (1990), which forbids employment discrimination
against "`all state employees, classified and exempt' on the basis of sexual orientation."
854 P.2d, at 1284. Also repealed, and now forbidden, are "various provisions prohibiting
discrimination based on sexual orientation at state colleges." Id., at 1284, 1285.
The repeal of these measures and the prohibition against their future reenactment
demonstrates that Amendment 2 has the same force and effect in Colorado's governmental
sector as it does elsewhere and that it applies to policies as well as ordinary legislation.
Amendment 2's reach may not be limited to specific laws passed for the benefit of
gays and lesbians. It is a fair, if not necessary, inference from the broad language
of the amendment that it deprives gays and lesbians even of the protection [ ROMER
v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 8] of general laws and policies that prohibit arbitrary
discrimination in governmental and private settings. See, e.g., Colo. Rev. Stat. 24-4-106(7)
(1988) (agency action subject to judicial review under arbitrary and capricious standard);
18-8-405 (making it a criminal offense for a public servant knowingly, arbitrarily
or capriciously to refrain from performing a duty imposed on him by law); 10-3-1104(1)(f)
(prohibiting "unfair discrimination" in insurance); 4 Colo. Code of Regulations 801-1,
Policy 11-1 (1983) (prohibiting discrimination in state employment on grounds of specified
traits or "other non-merit factor"). At some point in the systematic administration
of these laws, an official must determine whether homosexuality is an arbitrary and
thus forbidden basis for decision. Yet a decision to that effect would itself amount
to a policy prohibiting discrimination on the basis of homosexuality, and so would
appear to be no more valid under Amendment 2 than the specific prohibitions against
discrimination the state court held invalid.
If this consequence follows from Amendment 2, as its broad language suggests, it
would compound the constitutional difficulties the law creates. The state court did
not decide whether the amendment has this effect, however, and neither need we. In
the course of rejecting the argument that Amendment 2 is intended to conserve resources
to fight discrimination against suspect classes, the Colorado Supreme Court made the
limited observation that the amendment is not intended to affect many anti-discrimination
laws protecting non-suspect classes, Romer II, 882 P.2d at 1346, n. 9. In our view
that does not resolve the issue. In any event, even if, as we doubt, homosexuals could
find some safe harbor in laws of general application, we cannot accept the view that
Amendment 2's prohibition on specific legal protections does no more than deprive
homosexuals of special rights. To the contrary, the amendment imposes a special disability
upon those persons alone. Homosexuals are forbidden the safeguards that others enjoy
or may seek without constraint. They can obtain specific protection against discrimination
only by [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 9] enlisting the citizenry of Colorado
to amend the state constitution or perhaps, on the State's view, by trying to pass
helpful laws of general applicability. This is so no matter how local or discrete
the harm, no matter how public and widespread the injury. We find nothing special
in the protections Amendment 2 withholds. These are protections taken for granted
by most people either because they already have them or do not need them; these are
protections against exclusion from an almost limitless number of transactions and
endeavors that constitute ordinary civic life in a free society.
III
The Fourteenth Amendment's promise that no person shall be denied the equal protection
of the laws must co-exist with the practical necessity that most legislation classifies
for one purpose or another, with resulting disadvantage to various groups or persons.
Personnel Administrator of Mass. v. Feeney, 442 U.S. 256, 271 - 272 (1979); F. S.
Royster Guano Co. v. Virginia, 253 U.S. 412, 415 (1920). We have attempted to reconcile
the principle with the reality by stating that, if a law neither burdens a fundamental
right nor targets a suspect class, we will uphold the legislative classification so
long as it bears a rational relation to some legitimate end. See, e.g., Heller v.
Doe, 509 U.S. ___, ___ (1993) (slip op., at 6).
Amendment 2 fails, indeed defies, even this conventional inquiry. First, the amendment
has the peculiar property of imposing a broad and undifferentiated disability on a
single named group, an exceptional and, as we shall explain, invalid form of legislation.
Second, its sheer breadth is so discontinuous with the reasons offered for it that
the amendment seems inexplicable by anything but animus toward the class that it affects;
it lacks a rational relationship to legitimate state interests.
Taking the first point, even in the ordinary equal protection case calling for the
most deferential of standards, we insist on knowing the relation between the classification
adopted and the [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 10] object to be attained.
The search for the link between classification and objective gives substance to the
Equal Protection Clause; it provides guidance and discipline for the legislature,
which is entitled to know what sorts of laws it can pass; and it marks the limits
of our own authority. In the ordinary case, a law will be sustained if it can be said
to advance a legitimate government interest, even if the law seems unwise or works
to the disadvantage of a particular group, or if the rationale for it seems tenuous.
See New Orleans v. Dukes, 427 U.S. 297 (1976) (tourism benefits justified classification
favoring pushcart vendors of certain longevity); Williamson v. Lee Optical of Okla.,
Inc., 348 U.S. 483 (1955) (assumed health concerns justified law favoring optometrists
over opticians); Railway Express Agency, Inc. v. New York, 336 U.S. 106 (1949) (potential
traffic hazards justified exemption of vehicles advertising the owner's products from
general advertising ban); Kotch v. Board of River Port Pilot Comm'rs for Port of New
Orleans, 330 U.S. 552 (1947) (licensing scheme that disfavored persons unrelated to
current river boat pilots justified by possible efficiency and safety benefits of
a closely knit pilotage system). The laws challenged in the cases just cited were
narrow enough in scope and grounded in a sufficient factual context for us to ascertain
that there existed some relation between the classification and the purpose it served.
By requiring that the classification bear a rational relationship to an independent
and legitimate legislative end, we ensure that classifications are not drawn for the
purpose of disadvantaging the group burdened by the law. See United States Railroad
Retirement Bd. v. Fritz, 449 U.S. 166, 181 (1980) (STEVENS, J., concurring) ("If the
adverse impact on the disfavored class is an apparent aim of the legislature, its
impartiality would be suspect.").
Amendment 2 confounds this normal process of judicial review. It is at once too narrow
and too broad. It identifies persons by a single trait and then denies them protection
across the board. The resulting disqualification of a class of persons from the right
to seek specific protection from the law [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 11]
is unprecedented in our jurisprudence. The absence of precedent for Amendment 2 is
itself instructive; "[d]iscriminations of an unusual character especially suggest
careful consideration to determine whether they are obnoxious to the constitutional
provision." Louisville Gas & Elec. Co. v. Coleman, 277 U.S. 32, 37-38 (1928).
It is not within our constitutional tradition to enact laws of this sort. Central
both to the idea of the rule of law and to our own Constitution's guarantee of equal
protection is the principle that government and each of its parts remain open on impartial
terms to all who seek its assistance. "`Equal protection of the laws is not achieved
through indiscriminate imposition of inequalities.'" Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U.S. 629,
635 (1950) (quoting Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. 1, 22 (1948)). Respect for this principle
explains why laws singling out a certain class of citizens for disfavored legal status
or general hardships are rare. A law declaring that in general it shall be more difficult
for one group of citizens than for all others to seek aid from the government is itself
a denial of equal protection of the laws in the most literal sense. "The guaranty
of `equal protection of the laws is a pledge of the protection of equal laws.'" Skinner
v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, 316 U.S. 535, 541 (1942) (quoting Yick Wo v. Hopkins,
118 U.S. 356, 369 (1886)).
Davis v. Beason, 133 U.S. 333 (1890), not cited by the parties but relied upon by
the dissent, is not evidence that Amendment 2 is within our constitutional tradition,
and any reliance upon it as authority for sustaining the amendment is misplaced. In
Davis, the Court approved an Idaho territorial statute denying Mormons, polygamists,
and advocates of polygamy the right to vote and to hold office because, as the Court
construed the statute, it "simply excludes from the privilege of voting, or of holding
any office of honor, trust or profit, those who have been convicted of certain offences,
and those who advocate a practical resistance to the laws of the Territory and justify
and approve the commission of crimes [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 12] forbidden
by it." Id., at 347. To the extent Davis held that persons advocating a certain practice
may be denied the right to vote, it is no longer good law. Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395
U.S. 444 (1969) (per curiam). To the extent it held that the groups designated in
the statute may be deprived of the right to vote because of their status, its ruling
could not stand without surviving strict scrutiny, a most doubtful outcome. Dunn v.
Blumstein, 405 U.S. 330, 337 (1972); cf. United States v. Brown, 381 U.S. 437 (1965);
United States v. Robel, 389 U.S. 258 (1967). To the extent Davis held that a convicted
felon may be denied the right to vote, its holding is not implicated by our decision
and is unexceptionable. See Richardson v. Ramirez, 418 U.S. 24 (1974).
A second and related point is that laws of the kind now before us raise the inevitable
inference that the disadvantage imposed is born of animosity toward the class of persons
affected. "[I]f the constitutional conception of `equal protection of the laws' means
anything, it must at the very least mean that a bare . . . desire to harm a politically
unpopular group cannot constitute a legitimate governmental interest." Department
of Agriculture v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 534 (1973). Even laws enacted for broad and
ambitious purposes often can be explained by reference to legitimate public policies
which justify the incidental disadvantages they impose on certain persons. Amendment
2, however, in making a general announcement that gays and lesbians shall not have
any particular protections from the law, inflicts on them immediate, continuing, and
real injuries that outrun and belie any legitimate justifications that may be claimed
for it. We conclude that, in addition to the far-reaching deficiencies of Amendment
2 that we have noted, the principles it offends, in another sense, are conventional
and venerable; a law must bear a rational relationship to a legitimate governmental
purpose, Kadrmas v. Dickinson Public Schools, 487 U.S. 450, 462 (1988), and Amendment
2 does not.
The primary rationale the State offers for Amendment 2 is respect for other citizens'
freedom of association, and in [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 13] particular
the liberties of landlords or employers who have personal or religious objections
to homosexuality. Colorado also cites its interest in conserving resources to fight
discrimination against other groups. The breadth of the Amendment is so far removed
from these particular justifications that we find it impossible to credit them. We
cannot say that Amendment 2 is directed to any identifiable legitimate purpose or
discrete objective. It is a status-based enactment divorced from any factual context
from which we could discern a relationship to legitimate state interests; it is a
classification of persons undertaken for its own sake, something the Equal Protection
Clause does not permit. "[C]lass legislation . . . [is] obnoxious to the prohibitions
of the Fourteenth Amendment . . . ." Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S., at 24.
We must conclude that Amendment 2 classifies homosexuals not to further a proper
legislative end but to make them unequal to everyone else. This Colorado cannot do.
A State cannot so deem a class of persons a stranger to its laws. Amendment 2 violates
the Equal Protection Clause, and the judgment of the Supreme Court of Colorado is
affirmed.
It is so ordered. [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 1]
JUSTICE SCALIA, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE and JUSTICE THOMAS join, dissenting.
The Court has mistaken a Kulturkampf for a fit of spite. The constitutional amendment
before us here is not the manifestation of a "`bare . . . desire to harm'" homosexuals,
ante, at 13, but is rather a modest attempt by seemingly tolerant Coloradans to preserve
traditional sexual mores against the efforts of a politically powerful minority to
revise those mores through use of the laws. That objective, and the means chosen to
achieve it, are not only unimpeachable under any constitutional doctrine hitherto
pronounced (hence the opinion's heavy reliance upon principles of righteousness rather
than judicial holdings); they have been specifically approved by the Congress of the
United States and by this Court.
In holding that homosexuality cannot be singled out for disfavorable treatment, the
Court contradicts a decision, unchallenged here, pronounced only 10 years ago, see
Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986), and places the prestige of this institution
behind the proposition that opposition to homosexuality is as reprehensible as racial
or religious bias. Whether it is or not is precisely the cultural debate that gave
rise to the Colorado constitutional amendment (and to the preferential laws against
which the amendment was directed). Since the Constitution of the United States says
nothing about [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 2] this subject, it is left
to be resolved by normal democratic means, including the democratic adoption of provisions
in state constitutions. This Court has no business imposing upon all Americans the
resolution favored by the elite class from which the Members of this institution are
selected, pronouncing that "animosity" toward homosexuality, ante, at 13, is evil.
I vigorously dissent.
I
Let me first discuss Part II of the Court's opinion, its longest section, which is
devoted to rejecting the State's arguments that Amendment 2 "puts gays and lesbians
in the same position as all other persons," and "does no more than deny homosexuals
special rights," ante, at 4. The Court concludes that this reading of Amendment 2's
language is "implausible" under the "authoritative construction" given Amendment 2
by the Supreme Court of Colorado. Ibid.
In reaching this conclusion, the Court considers it unnecessary to decide the validity
of the State's argument that Amendment 2 does not deprive homosexuals of the "protection
[afforded by] general laws and policies that prohibit arbitrary discrimination in
governmental and private settings." Ante, at 8. I agree that we need not resolve that
dispute, because the Supreme Court of Colorado has resolved it for us. In Evans v.
Romer, 882 P.2d 1335 (1994), the Colorado court stated:
"[I]t is significant to note that Colorado law currently proscribes discrimination
against persons who are not suspect classes, including discrimination based on age,
24-34-402(1)(a), 10A C. R. S. (1994 Supp.); marital or family status, 24-34-502(1)(a),
10A C. R. S. (1994 Supp.); veterans' status, 28-3-506, 11B C. R. S. (1989); and for
any legal, off-duty conduct such as smoking tobacco, 24-34-402.5, 10A C. R. S. (1994
Supp.). Of course Amendment 2 is not intended to have any effect on this legislation,
but seeks only to prevent the adoption of anti-discrimination laws intended to protect
gays, lesbians, and [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 3] bisexuals." Id., at
1346, n. 9 (emphasis added).
The Court utterly fails to distinguish this portion of the Colorado court's opinion.
Colorado Rev. Stat. 24-34-402.5 (Supp. 1995), which this passage authoritatively declares
not to be affected by Amendment 2, was respondents' primary example of a generally
applicable law whose protections would be unavailable to homosexuals under Amendment
2. See Brief for Respondents Evans et al. 11-12. The clear import of the Colorado
court's conclusion that it is not affected is that "general laws and policies that
prohibit arbitrary discrimination" would continue to prohibit discrimination on the
basis of homosexual conduct as well. This analysis, which is fully in accord with
(indeed, follows inescapably from) the text of the constitutional provision, lays
to rest such horribles, raised in the course of oral argument, as the prospect that
assaults upon homosexuals could not be prosecuted. The amendment prohibits special
treatment of homosexuals, and nothing more. It would not affect, for example, a requirement
of state law that pensions be paid to all retiring state employees with a certain
length of service; homosexual employees, as well as others, would be entitled to that
benefit. But it would prevent the State or any municipality from making death-benefit
payments to the "life partner" of a homosexual when it does not make such payments
to the long-time roommate of a nonhomosexual employee. Or again, it does not affect
the requirement of the State's general insurance laws that customers be afforded coverage
without discrimination unrelated to anticipated risk. Thus, homosexuals could not
be denied coverage, or charged a greater premium, with respect to auto collision insurance;
but neither the State nor any municipality could require that distinctive health insurance
risks associated with homosexuality (if there are any) be ignored.
Despite all of its hand-wringing about the potential effect of Amendment 2 on general
antidiscrimination laws, the Court's opinion ultimately does not dispute all this,
but assumes it to [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 4] be true. See ante, at
9. The only denial of equal treatment it contends homosexuals have suffered is this:
They may not obtain preferential treatment without amending the state constitution.
That is to say, the principle underlying the Court's opinion is that one who is accorded
equal treatment under the laws, but cannot as readily as others obtain preferential
treatment under the laws, has been denied equal protection of the laws. If merely
stating this alleged "equal protection" violation does not suffice to refute it, our
constitutional jurisprudence has achieved terminal silliness.
The central thesis of the Court's reasoning is that any group is denied equal protection
when, to obtain advantage (or, presumably, to avoid disadvantage), it must have recourse
to a more general and hence more difficult level of political decisionmaking than
others. The world has never heard of such a principle, which is why the Court's opinion
is so long on emotive utterance and so short on relevant legal citation. And it seems
to me most unlikely that any multilevel democracy can function under such a principle.
For whenever a disadvantage is imposed, or conferral of a benefit is prohibited, at
one of the higher levels of democratic decisionmaking (i.e., by the state legislature
rather than local government, or by the people at large in the state constitution
rather than the legislature), the affected group has (under this theory) been denied
equal protection. To take the simplest of examples, consider a state law prohibiting
the award of municipal contracts to relatives of mayors or city councilmen. Once such
a law is passed, the group composed of such relatives must, in order to get the benefit
of city contracts, persuade the state legislature - unlike all other citizens, who
need only persuade the municipality. It is ridiculous to consider this a denial of
equal protection, which is why the Court's theory is unheard-of.
The Court might reply that the example I have given is not a denial of equal protection
only because the same "rational basis" (avoidance of corruption) which renders constitutional
the substantive discrimination against relatives (i.e., the fact [ ROMER v. EVANS,
___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 5] that they alone cannot obtain city contracts) also automatically
suffices to sustain what might be called the electoral-procedural discrimination against
them (i.e., the fact that they must go to the state level to get this changed). This
is of course a perfectly reasonable response, and would explain why "electoral-procedural
discrimination" has not hitherto been heard of: a law that is valid in its substance
is automatically valid in its level of enactment. But the Court cannot afford to make
this argument, for as I shall discuss next, there is no doubt of a rational basis
for the substance of the prohibition at issue here. The Court's entire novel theory
rests upon the proposition that there is something special - something that cannot
be justified by normal "rational basis" analysis - in making a disadvantaged group
(or a nonpreferred group) resort to a higher decisionmaking level. That proposition
finds no support in law or logic.
II
I turn next to whether there was a legitimate rational basis for the substance of
the constitutional amendment - for the prohibition of special protection for homosexuals.
1 It is unsurprising that the Court avoids discussion of this question, since the
answer is so obviously yes. The case most relevant to the issue before us today is
not even mentioned in the Court's opinion: In Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986),
we held that the Constitution does not prohibit what virtually all States had done
from the founding of the Republic [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 6] until
very recent years - making homosexual conduct a crime. That holding is unassailable,
except by those who think that the Constitution changes to suit current fashions.
But in any event it is a given in the present case: Respondents' briefs did not urge
overruling Bowers, and at oral argument respondents' counsel expressly disavowed any
intent to seek such overruling, Tr. of Oral Arg. 53. If it is constitutionally permissible
for a State to make homosexual conduct criminal, surely it is constitutionally permissible
for a State to enact other laws merely disfavoring homosexual conduct. (As the Court
of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit has aptly put it: "If the Court [in
Bowers] was unwilling to object to state laws that criminalize the behavior that defines
the class, it is hardly open . . . to conclude that state sponsored discrimination
against the class is invidious. After all, there can hardly be more palpable discrimination
against a class than making the conduct that defines the class criminal." Padula v.
Webster, 822 F.2d 97, 103 (1987).) And a fortiori it is constitutionally permissible
for a State to adopt a provision not even disfavoring homosexual conduct, but merely
prohibiting all levels of state government from bestowing special protections upon
homosexual conduct. Respondents (who, unlike the Court, cannot afford the luxury of
ignoring inconvenient precedent) counter Bowers with the argument that a greater-includes-the-lesser
rationale cannot justify Amendment 2's application to individuals who do not engage
in homosexual acts, but are merely of homosexual "orientation." Some courts of appeals
have concluded that, with respect to laws of this sort at least, that is a distinction
without a difference. See Equality Foundation of Greater Cincinnati, Inc. v. Cincinnati,
54 F.3d 261, 267 (CA6 1995) ("[F]or purposes of these proceedings, it is virtually
impossible to distinguish or separate individuals of a particular orientation which
predisposes them toward a particular sexual conduct from those who actually engage
in that particular type of sexual conduct"); Steffan v. Perry, 41 F.3d 677, 689-690
(CADC 1994). The Supreme Court of Colorado itself appears to be of this view. [ ROMER
v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 7] See 882 P.2d, at 1349-1350 ("Amendment 2 targets
this class of persons based on four characteristics: sexual orientation; conduct;
practices; and relationships. Each characteristic provides a potentially different
way of identifying that class of persons who are gay, lesbian, or bisexual. These
four characteristics are not truly severable from one another because each provides
nothing more than a different way of identifying the same class of persons") (emphasis
added).
But assuming that, in Amendment 2, a person of homosexual "orientation" is someone
who does not engage in homosexual conduct but merely has a tendency or desire to do
so, Bowers still suffices to establish a rational basis for the provision. If it is
rational to criminalize the conduct, surely it is rational to deny special favor and
protection to those with a self-avowed tendency or desire to engage in the conduct.
Indeed, where criminal sanctions are not involved, homosexual "orientation" is an
acceptable stand-in for homosexual conduct. A State "does not violate the Equal Protection
Clause merely because the classifications made by its laws are imperfect," Dandridge
v. Williams, 397 U.S. 471, 485 (1970). Just as a policy barring the hiring of methadone
users as transit employees does not violate equal protection simply because some methadone
users pose no threat to passenger safety, see New York City Transit Authority v. Beazer,
440 U.S. 568 (1979), and just as a mandatory retirement age of 50 for police officers
does not violate equal protection even though it prematurely ends the careers of many
policemen over 50 who still have the capacity to do the job, see Massachusetts Bd.
of Retirement v. Murgia, 427 U.S. 307 (1976) (per curiam), Amendment 2 is not constitutionally
invalid simply because it could have been drawn more precisely so as to withdraw special
antidiscrimination protections only from those of homosexual "orientation" who actually
engage in homosexual conduct. As JUSTICE KENNEDY wrote, when he was on the Court of
Appeals, in a case involving discharge of homosexuals from the Navy: "Nearly any statute
which classifies people may be irrational as applied [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___
(1996) , 8] in particular cases. Discharge of the particular plaintiffs before us
would be rational, under minimal scrutiny, not because their particular cases present
the dangers which justify Navy policy, but instead because the general policy of discharging
all homosexuals is rational." Beller v. Middendorf, 632 F.2d 788, 808-809, n. 20 (CA9
1980) (citation omitted). See also Ben-Shalom v. Marsh, 881 F.2d 454, 464 (CA7 1989),
cert. denied, 494 U.S. 1004 (1990).
Moreover, even if the provision regarding homosexual "orientation" were invalid,
respondents' challenge to Amendment 2 - which is a facial challenge must fail. "A
facial challenge to a legislative Act is, of course, the most difficult challenge
to mount successfully, since the challenger must establish that no set of circumstances
exists under which the Act would be valid." United States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739,
745 (1987). It would not be enough for respondents to establish (if they could) that
Amendment 2 is unconstitutional as applied to those of homosexual "orientation"; since,
under Bowers, Amendment 2 is unquestionably constitutional as applied to those who
engage in homosexual conduct, the facial challenge cannot succeed. Some individuals
of homosexual "orientation" who do not engage in homosexual acts might successfully
bring an as-applied challenge to Amendment 2, but so far as the record indicates,
none of the respondents is such a person. See App. 4-5 (complaint describing each
of the individual respondents as either "a gay man" or "a lesbian"). 2 [ ROMER v.
EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 9]
III
The foregoing suffices to establish what the Court's failure to cite any case remotely
in point would lead one to suspect: No principle set forth in the Constitution, nor
even any imagined by this Court in the past 200 years, prohibits what Colorado has
done here. But the case for Colorado is much stronger than that. What it has done
is not only unprohibited, but eminently reasonable, with close, congressionally approved
precedent in earlier constitutional practice.
First, as to its eminent reasonableness. The Court's opinion contains grim, disapproving
hints that Coloradans have been guilty of "animus" or "animosity" toward homosexuality,
as though that has been established as Unamerican. Of course it is our moral heritage
that one should not hate any human being or class of human beings. But I had thought
that one could consider certain conduct reprehensible - murder, for example, or polygamy,
or cruelty to animals - and could exhibit even "animus" toward such conduct. Surely
that is the only sort of "animus" at issue here: moral disapproval of homosexual conduct,
the same sort of moral disapproval that produced the centuries-old criminal laws that
we held constitutional in Bowers. The Colorado amendment does not, to speak entirely
precisely, prohibit giving favored status to people who are homosexuals; they can
be favored for many reasons - for example, because they are senior citizens or members
of racial minorities. But it prohibits giving them favored status because of their
homosexual conduct - that is, it prohibits favored status for homosexuality.
But though Coloradans are, as I say, entitled to be hostile toward homosexual conduct,
the fact is that the degree of hostility reflected by Amendment 2 is the smallest
conceivable. The Court's portrayal of Coloradans as a society fallen victim [ ROMER
v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 10] to pointless, hate-filled "gay-bashing" is so
false as to be comical. Colorado not only is one of the 25 States that have repealed
their antisodomy laws, but was among the first to do so. See 1971 Colo. Sess. Laws,
ch. 121, 1. But the society that eliminates criminal punishment for homosexual acts
does not necessarily abandon the view that homosexuality is morally wrong and socially
harmful; often, abolition simply reflects the view that enforcement of such criminal
laws involves unseemly intrusion into the intimate lives of citizens. Cf. Brief for
Lambda Legal Defense and Education Fund, Inc., et al. as Amici Curiae in Bowers v.
Hardwick, O. T. 1985, No. 85-140, p. 25, n. 21 (antisodomy statutes are "unenforceable
by any but the most offensive snooping and wasteful allocation of law enforcement
resources"); Kadish, The Crisis of Overcriminalization, 374 The Annals of the American
Academy of Political and Social Science 157, 161 (1967) ("To obtain evidence [in sodomy
cases], police are obliged to resort to behavior which tends to degrade and demean
both themselves personally and law enforcement as an institution").
There is a problem, however, which arises when criminal sanction of homosexuality
is eliminated but moral and social disapprobation of homosexuality is meant to be
retained. The Court cannot be unaware of that problem; it is evident in many cities
of the country, and occasionally bubbles to the surface of the news, in heated political
disputes over such matters as the introduction into local schools of books teaching
that homosexuality is an optional and fully acceptable "alternate life style." The
problem (a problem, that is, for those who wish to retain social disapprobation of
homosexuality) is that, because those who engage in homosexual conduct tend to reside
in disproportionate numbers in certain communities, see Record, Exh. MMM, have high
disposable income, see ibid.; App. 254 (affidavit of Prof. James Hunter), and of course
care about homosexual-rights issues much more ardently than the public at large, they
possess political power much greater than their numbers, both locally and statewide.
Quite understandably, they devote this political power to achieving [ ROMER v. EVANS,
___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 11] not merely a grudging social toleration, but full social
acceptance, of homosexuality. See, e.g., Jacobs, The Rhetorical Construction of Rights:
The Case of the Gay Rights Movement, 1969-1991, 72 Neb. L. Rev. 723, 724 (1993) ("[T]he
task of gay rights proponents is to move the center of public discourse along a continuum
from the rhetoric of disapprobation, to rhetoric of tolerance, and finally to affirmation").
By the time Coloradans were asked to vote on Amendment 2, their exposure to homosexuals'
quest for social endorsement was not limited to newspaper accounts of happenings in
places such as New York, Los Angeles, San Francisco, and Key West. Three Colorado
cities - Aspen, Boulder, and Denver had enacted ordinances that listed "sexual orientation"
as an impermissible ground for discrimination, equating the moral disapproval of homosexual
conduct with racial and religious bigotry. See Aspen Municipal Code 13-98 (1977);
Boulder Rev. Municipal Code 12-1-1 to 12-1-11 (1987); Denver Rev. Municipal Code,
Art. IV 28-91 to 28-116 (1991). The phenomenon had even appeared statewide: the Governor
of Colorado had signed an executive order pronouncing that "in the State of Colorado
we recognize the diversity in our pluralistic society and strive to bring an end to
discrimination in any form," and directing state agency-heads to "ensure non-discrimination"
in hiring and promotion based on, among other things, "sexual orientation." Executive
Order No. D0035 (Dec. 10, 1990). I do not mean to be critical of these legislative
successes; homosexuals are as entitled to use the legal system for reinforcement of
their moral sentiments as are the rest of society. But they are subject to being countered
by lawful, democratic countermeasures as well.
That is where Amendment 2 came in. It sought to counter both the geographic concentration
and the disproportionate political power of homosexuals by (1) resolving the controversy
at the statewide level, and (2) making the election a single-issue contest for both
sides. It put directly, to all the citizens of the State, the question: Should homosexuality
be given [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 12] special protection? They answered
no. The Court today asserts that this most democratic of procedures is unconstitutional.
Lacking any cases to establish that facially absurd proposition, it simply asserts
that it must be unconstitutional, because it has never happened before.
"[Amendment 2] identifies persons by a single trait and then denies them protection
across the board. The resulting disqualification of a class of persons from the right
to seek specific protection from the law is unprecedented in our jurisprudence. The
absence of precedent for Amendment 2 is itself instructive . . . .
"It is not within our constitutional tradition to enact laws of this sort. Central
both to the idea of the rule of law and to our own Constitution's guarantee of equal
protection is the principle that government and each of its parts remain open on impartial
terms to all who seek its assistance." Ante, at 11-12.
As I have noted above, this is proved false every time a state law prohibiting or
disfavoring certain conduct is passed, because such a law prevents the adversely affected
group whether drug addicts, or smokers, or gun owners, or motorcyclists - from changing
the policy thus established in "each of [the] parts" of the State. What the Court
says is even demonstrably false at the constitutional level. The Eighteenth Amendment
to the Federal Constitution, for example, deprived those who drank alcohol not only
of the power to alter the policy of prohibition locally or through state legislation,
but even of the power to alter it through state constitutional amendment or federal
legislation. The Establishment Clause of the First Amendment prevents theocrats from
having their way by converting their fellow citizens at the local, state, or federal
statutory level; as does the Republican Form of Government Clause prevent monarchists.
[ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 13]
But there is a much closer analogy, one that involves precisely the effort by the
majority of citizens to preserve its view of sexual morality statewide, against the
efforts of a geographically concentrated and politically powerful minority to undermine
it. The constitutions of the States of Arizona, Idaho, New Mexico, Oklahoma, and Utah
to this day contain provisions stating that polygamy is "forever prohibited." See
Ariz. Const., Art. XX, par. 2; Idaho Const., Art. I, 4; N. M. Const., Art. XXI, 1;
Okla. Const., Art. I, 2; Utah Const., Art. III, 1. Polygamists, and those who have
a polygamous "orientation," have been "singled out" by these provisions for much more
severe treatment than merely denial of favored status; and that treatment can only
be changed by achieving amendment of the state constitutions. The Court's disposition
today suggests that these provisions are unconstitutional, and that polygamy must
be permitted in these States on a state-legislated, or perhaps even local-option,
basis - unless, of course, polygamists for some reason have fewer constitutional rights
than homosexuals.
The United States Congress, by the way, required the inclusion of these antipolygamy
provisions in the constitutions of Arizona, New Mexico, Oklahoma, and Utah, as a condition
of their admission to statehood. See Arizona Enabling Act, 36 Stat. 569; New Mexico
Enabling Act, 36 Stat. 558; Oklahoma Enabling Act, 34 Stat. 269; Utah Enabling Act,
28 Stat. 108. (For Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah, moreover, the Enabling Acts required
that the antipolygamy provisions be "irrevocable without the consent of the United
States and the people of said State" - so that not only were "each of [the] parts"
of these States not "open on impartial terms" to polygamists, but even the States
as a whole were not; polygamists would have to persuade the whole country to their
way of thinking.) Idaho adopted the constitutional provision on its own, but the 51st
Congress, which admitted Idaho into the Union, found its constitution to be "republican
in form and . . . in conformity with the Constitution of the United States." Act of
Admission of Idaho, 26 Stat. 215 (emphasis [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) ,
14] added). Thus, this "singling out" of the sexual practices of a single group for
statewide, democratic vote - so utterly alien to our constitutional system, the Court
would have us believe - has not only happened, but has received the explicit approval
of the United States Congress.
I cannot say that this Court has explicitly approved any of these state constitutional
provisions; but it has approved a territorial statutory provision that went even further,
depriving polygamists of the ability even to achieve a constitutional amendment, by
depriving them of the power to vote. In Davis v. Beason, 133 U.S. 333 (1890), Justice
Field wrote for a unanimous Court:
"In our judgment, 501 of the Revised Statutes of Idaho Territory, which provides
that `no person . . . who is a bigamist or polygamist or who teaches, advises, counsels,
or encourages any person or persons to become bigamists or polygamists, or to commit
any other crime defined by law, or to enter into what is known as plural or celestial
marriage, or who is a member of any order, organization or association which teaches,
advises, counsels, or encourages its members or devotees or any other persons to commit
the crime of bigamy or polygamy, or any other crime defined by law . . . is permitted
to vote at any election, or to hold any position or office of honor, trust, or profit
within this Territory,' is not open to any constitutional or legal objection." Id.,
at 346-347 (emphasis added).
To the extent, if any, that this opinion permits the imposition of adverse consequences
upon mere abstract advocacy of polygamy, it has of course been overruled by later
cases. See Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444 (1969) (per curiam). But the proposition
that polygamy can be criminalized, and those engaging in that crime deprived of the
vote, remains good law. See Richardson v. Ramirez, 418 U.S. 24, 53 (1974). Beason
rejected the argument that "such discrimination is a denial of the equal protection
of the laws." Brief [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 15] for Appellant in Davis
v. Beason, O. T. 1889, No. 1261, p. 41. Among the Justices joining in that rejection
were the two whose views in other cases the Court today treats as equal-protection
lodestars - Justice Harlan, who was to proclaim in Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537,
559 (1896) (dissenting opinion), that the Constitution "neither knows nor tolerates
classes among citizens," quoted ante, at 1, and Justice Bradley, who had earlier declared
that "class legislation . . . [is] obnoxious to the prohibitions of the Fourteenth
Amendment," Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S. 3, 24 (1883), quoted ante, at 14. 3
This Court cited Beason with approval as recently as 1993, in an opinion authored
by the same Justice who writes for the [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 16]
Court today. That opinion said: "[A]dverse impact will not always lead to a finding
of impermissible targeting. For example, a social harm may have been a legitimate
concern of government for reasons quite apart from discrimination. . . . See, e.g.,
. . . Davis v. Beason, 133 U.S. 333 (1890)." Church of Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v.
Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520, 535 (1993). It remains to be explained how 501 of the Idaho
Revised Statutes was not an "impermissible targeting" of polygamists, but (the much
more mild) Amendment 2 is an "impermissible targeting" of homosexuals. Has the Court
concluded that the perceived social harm of polygamy is a "legitimate concern of government,"
and the perceived social harm of homosexuality is not?
IV
I strongly suspect that the answer to the last question is yes, which leads me to
the last point I wish to make: The Court today, announcing that Amendment 2 "defies
. . . conventional [constitutional] inquiry," ante, at 10, and "confounds [the] normal
process of judicial review," ante, at 11, employs a constitutional theory heretofore
unknown to frustrate Colorado's reasonable effort to preserve traditional American
moral values. The Court's stern disapproval of "animosity" towards homosexuality might
be compared with what an earlier Court (including the revered Justices Harlan and
Bradley) said in Murphy v. Ramsey, 114 U.S. 15 (1885), rejecting a constitutional
challenge to a United States statute that denied the franchise in federal territories
to those who engaged in polygamous cohabitation:
"[C]ertainly no legislation can be supposed more wholesome and necessary in the founding
of a free, self-governing commonwealth, fit to take rank as one of the co-ordinate
States of the Union, than that which seeks to establish it on the basis of the idea
of the family, as consisting in and springing from the union for life of one man and
one woman in the holy estate of matrimony; the sure foundation of all that is stable
and noble in our [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 17] civilization; the best
guaranty of that reverent morality which is the source of all beneficent progress
in social and political improvement." Id., at 45.
I would not myself indulge in such official praise for heterosexual monogamy, because
I think it no business of the courts (as opposed to the political branches) to take
sides in this culture war.
But the Court today has done so, not only by inventing a novel and extravagant constitutional
doctrine to take the victory away from traditional forces, but even by verbally disparaging
as bigotry adherence to traditional attitudes. To suggest, for example, that this
constitutional amendment springs from nothing more than "`a bare . . . desire to harm
a politically unpopular group,'" ante, at 13, quoting Department of Agriculture v.
Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 534 (1973), is nothing short of insulting. (It is also nothing
short of preposterous to call "politically unpopular" a group which enjoys enormous
influence in American media and politics, and which, as the trial court here noted,
though composing no more than 4% of the population had the support of 46% of the voters
on Amendment 2, see App. to Pet. for Cert. C-18.)
When the Court takes sides in the culture wars, it tends to be with the knights rather
than the villeins - and more specifically with the Templars, reflecting the views
and values of the lawyer class from which the Court's Members are drawn. How that
class feels about homosexuality will be evident to anyone who wishes to interview
job applicants at virtually any of the Nation's law schools. The interviewer may refuse
to offer a job because the applicant is a Republican; because he is an adulterer;
because he went to the wrong prep school or belongs to the wrong country club; because
he eats snails; because he is a womanizer; because she wears real-animal fur; or even
because he hates the Chicago Cubs. But if the interviewer should wish not to be an
associate or partner of an applicant because he disapproves of the [ ROMER v. EVANS,
___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 18] applicant's homosexuality, then he will have violated the
pledge which the Association of American Law Schools requires all its member-schools
to exact from job interviewers: "assurance of the employer's willingness" to hire
homosexuals. Bylaws of the Association of American Law Schools, Inc. 6-4(b); Executive
Committee Regulations of the Association of American Law Schools 6.19, in 1995 Handbook,
Association of American Law Schools. This law-school view of what "prejudices" must
be stamped out may be contrasted with the more plebeian attitudes that apparently
still prevail in the United States Congress, which has been unresponsive to repeated
attempts to extend to homosexuals the protections of federal civil rights laws, see,
e.g., Employment Non-Discrimination Act of 1994, S. 2238, 103d Cong., 2d Sess. (1994);
Civil Rights Amendments of 1975, H. R. 5452, 94th Cong., 1st Sess. (1975), and which
took the pains to exclude them specifically from the Americans With Disabilities Act
of 1990, see 42 U.S.C. 12211(a) (1988 ed., Supp. V).
* * *
Today's opinion has no foundation in American constitutional law, and barely pretends
to. The people of Colorado have adopted an entirely reasonable provision which does
not even disfavor homosexuals in any substantive sense, but merely denies them preferential
treatment. Amendment 2 is designed to prevent piecemeal deterioration of the sexual
morality favored by a majority of Coloradans, and is not only an appropriate means
to that legitimate end, but a means that Americans have employed before. Striking
it down is an act, not of judicial judgment, but of political will. I dissent.
Footnotes
[ Footnote 1 ] The Court evidently agrees that "rational basis" - the normal test
for compliance with the Equal Protection Clause - is the governing standard. The trial
court rejected respondents' argument that homosexuals constitute a "suspect" or "quasi-suspect"
class, and respondents elected not to appeal that ruling to the Supreme Court of Colorado.
See Evans v. Romer, 882 P.2d 1335, 1341, n. 3 (1994). And the Court implicitly rejects
the Supreme Court of Colorado's holding, see Evans v. Romer, 854 P.2d 1270, 1282 (1993),
that Amendment 2 infringes upon a "fundamental right" of "independently identifiable
class[es]" to "participate equally in the political process." Ante, at 4.
[ Footnote 2 ] The Supreme Court of Colorado stated: "We hold that the portions of
Amendment 2 that would remain if only the provision concerning sexual orientation
were stricken are not autonomous and thus, not severable," 882 P.2d, at 1349. That
statement was premised, however, on the proposition that "[the] four characteristics
[described in the Amendment - sexual orientation, conduct, practices, and relationships]
are not truly severable from one another because each provides nothing more than a
different way of identifying the same class of persons." Id., at 1349-1350 (emphasis
added). As I have discussed above, if that premise is true - if the entire class affected
by the Amendment takes part in homosexual conduct, practices and relationships - Bowers
alone suffices to answer all [ ROMER v. EVANS, ___ U.S. ___ (1996) , 9] constitutional
objections. Separate consideration of persons of homosexual "orientation" is necessary
only if one believes (as the Supreme Court of Colorado did not) that that is a distinct
class.
[ Footnote 3 ] The Court labors mightily to get around Beason, see ante, at 12-13,
but cannot escape the central fact that this Court found the statute at issue - which
went much further than Amendment 2, denying polygamists not merely special treatment
but the right to vote - "not open to any constitutional or legal objection," rejecting
the appellant's argument (much like the argument of respondents today) that the statute
impermissibly "single[d] him out," Brief for Appellant in Davis v. Beason, O. T. 1889,
No. 1261, p. 41. The Court adopts my conclusions that (a) insofar as Beason permits
the imposition of adverse consequences based upon mere advocacy, it has been overruled
by subsequent cases, and (b) insofar as Beason holds that convicted felons may be
denied the right to vote, it remains good law. To these conclusions, it adds something
new: the claim that "[t]o the extent [Beason] held that the groups designated in the
statute may be deprived of the right to vote because of their status, its ruling could
not stand without surviving strict scrutiny, a most doubtful outcome." Ante, at 12-13.
But if that is so, it is only because we have declared the right to vote to be a "fundamental
political right," see, e.g., Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.S. 330, 336 (1972), deprivation
of which triggers strict scrutiny. Amendment 2, of course, does not deny the fundamental
right to vote, and the Court rejects the Colorado court's view that there exists a
fundamental right to participate in the political process. Strict scrutiny is thus
not in play here. See ante, at 10. Finally, the Court's suggestion that 501 of the
Revised Statutes of Idaho, and Amendment 2, deny rights on account of "status" (rather
than conduct) opens up a broader debate involving the significance of Bowers to this
case, a debate which the Court is otherwise unwilling to join, see supra, at 6-9.
Page I