Constitutional Law Cases: Rehnquist Court
1990 - 1999
ALDEN et al. v. MAINE
certiorari to the supreme judicial court of maine
No. 98-436.
Argued March 31, 1999
Decided June 23, 1999
After this Court decided, in Seminole Tribe of Fla. v. Florida, 517 U. S. 44 , that
Congress lacks power under Article I to abrogate the States' sovereign immunity in
federal court, the Federal District Court dismissed a Fair Labor Standards Act of
1938 suit filed by petitioners against their employer, respondent Maine. Subsequently,
petitioners filed the same action in state court. Although the FLSA purports to authorize
private actions against States in their own courts, the trial court dismissed the
suit on the ground of sovereign immunity. The Maine Supreme Judicial Court affirmed.
Held:
1. The Constitution's structure and history and this Court's authoritative interpretations
make clear that the States' immunity from suit is a fundamental aspect of the sovereignty
they enjoyed before the Constitution's ratification and retain today except as altered
by the plan of the Convention or certain constitutional Amendments. Under the federal
system established by the Constitution, the States retain a "residuary and inviolable
sovereignty." The Federalist No. 39, p. 245. They are not relegated to the role of
mere provinces or political corporations, but retain the dignity, though not the full
authority, of sovereignty. The founding generation considered immunity from private
suits central to this dignity. The doctrine that a sovereign could not be sued without
its consent was universal in the States when the Constitution was drafted and ratified.
In addition, the leading advocates of the Constitution gave explicit assurances during
the ratification debates that the Constitution would not strip States of sovereign
immunity. This was also the understanding of those state conventions that addressed
state sovereign immunity in their ratification documents. When, just five years after
the Constitution's adoption, this Court held that Article III authorized a private
citizen of another State to sue Georgia without its consent, Chisholm v. Georgia,
2 Dall. 419, the Eleventh Amendment was ratified. An examination of Chisholm indicates
that the case, not the Amendment, deviated from the original understanding, which
was to preserve States' traditional immunity from suit. The Amendment's text and history
also suggest that Congress acted not to change but to restore the original constitutional
design. Finally, the swiftness and near unanimity with which the Amendment was adopted
indicate that the Court had not captured the original understanding. This Court's
subsequent decisions reflect a settled doctrinal understanding that sovereign immunity
derives not from the Eleventh Amendment but from the structure of the original Constitution.
Since the Amendment confirmed rather than established sovereign immunity as a constitutional
principal, it follows that that immunity's scope is demarcated not by the text of
the Amendment alone but by fundamental postulates implicit in the constitutional design.
Pp. 3-20.
2. The States' immunity from private suit in their own courts is beyond congressional
power to abrogate by Article I legislation. Pp. 20-45.
(a) Congress may exercise its Article I powers to subject States to private suits
in their own courts only if there is compelling evidence that States were required
to surrender this power to Congress pursuant to the constitutional design. Blatchford
v. Native Village of Noatak, 501 U. S. 775, 781 . Pp. 20-21.
(b) Neither the Constitution's text nor the Court's recent sovereign immunity decisions
establish that States were required to relinquish this portion of their sovereignty.
Pp. 21-31.
(1) The Constitution, by delegating to Congress the power to establish the supreme
law of the land when acting within its enumerated powers, does not foreclose a State
from asserting immunity to claims arising under federal law merely because that law
derives not from the State itself but from the national power. See, e.g., Hans v.
Louisiana, 134 U. S. 1 . Moreover, the specific Article I powers delegated to Congress
do not necessarily include the incidental authority to subject States to private suits
as a means of achieving objectives otherwise within the enumerated powers' scope.
Those decisions that have endorsed this contention, see, e.g., Parden v. Terminal
R. Co. of Ala. Docks Dept., 377 U. S. 184, 190-194 , have been overruled, see, e.g.,
College Savings Bank v. Florida Prepaid Postsecondary Ed. Expense Bd., ante, at ___.
Pp. 21-26.
(2) Isolated statements in some of this Court's cases suggest that the Eleventh Amendment
is inapplicable in state courts. This is a truism as to the Amendment's literal terms.
However, the Amendment's bare text is not an exhaustive description of States' constitutional
immunity, and the cases do not decide the question whether States retain immunity
in their own courts notwithstanding an attempted abrogation by Congress. Pp. 26-31.
(c) Whether Congress has the authority under Article I to abrogate a State's immunity
in its own courts is, then, a question of first impression. History, practice, precedent,
and the Constitution's structure show no compelling evidence that this derogation
of the States' sovereignty is inherent in the constitutional compact. Pp.
31-48.
(1) Turning first to evidence of the original understanding of the Constitution:
The founders silence regarding the States' immunity from suit in their own courts,
despite the controversy regarding state sovereign immunity in federal court, suggests
the sovereign's right to assert immunity from suit in its own courts was so well established
that no one conceived the new Constitution would alter it. The arguments raised for
and against the Constitution during ratification confirm this strong inference. Similarly,
nothing in Chisholm, the catalyst for the Eleventh Amendment, suggested the States
were not immune from suits in their own courts. The Amendment's language, furthermore,
was directed toward Article III, the only constitutional provision believed to call
state sovereign immunity into question; and nothing in that Article suggested the
States could not assert immunity in their own courts or that Congress had the power
to abrogate such immunity. Finally, implicit in a proposal rejected by Congress--which
would have limited the Amendment's scope to cases where States had made available
a remedy in their own courts--was the premise that States retained their immunity
and the concomitant authority to decide whether to allow private suits against the
sovereign in their own courts. Pp. 31-34.
(2) The historical analysis is supported by early congressional practice. Early Congresses
enacted no statutes purporting to authorize suits against nonconsenting States in
state court, and statutes purporting to authorize such suits in any forum are all
but absent in the Nation's historical experience. Even recent statutes provide no
evidence of an understanding that Congress has a greater power to subject States to
suit in their own courts than in federal courts. Pp. 34-35.
(3) The theory and reasoning of this Court's earlier cases also suggest that States
retain constitutional immunity from suit in their own courts. The States' immunity
has been described in sweeping terms, without reference to whether a suit was prosecuted
in state or federal court. See, e.g., Briscoe v. Bank of Kentucky, 11 Pet. 257, 321-322.
The Court has said on many occasions that the States retain their immunity in their
own courts, see, e.g., Beers v. Arkansas, 20 How. 527, 529, and has relied on that
as a premise in its Eleventh Amendment rulings, see, e.g., Hans v. Louisiana, supra,
at 10. Pp. 35-39.
(4) A review of the essential principles of federalism and the state courts' special
role in the constitutional design leads to the conclusion that a congressional power
to subject nonconsenting States to private suits in their own courts is inconsistent
with the Constitution's structure.
Federalism requires that Congress accord States the respect and dignity due them
as residuary sovereigns and joint participants in the Nation's governance. Immunity
from suit in federal courts is not enough to preserve that dignity, for the indignity
of subjecting a nonconsenting State to the coercive process of judicial tribunals
at the instance of private parties exists regardless of the forum. In some ways, a
congressional power to authorize suits against States in their own courts would be
even more offensive to state sovereignty than a power to authorize suits in a federal
forum, since a sovereign's immunity in its own courts has always been understood to
be within the sole control of the sovereign itself. Further, because the Federal Government
retains its own immunity from suit in state and federal court, this Court is reluctant
to conclude that States are not entitled to a reciprocal privilege. Underlying constitutional
form are considerations of great substance. Private suits against nonconsenting States
may threaten their financial integrity, and the surrender of immunity carries with
it substantial costs to the autonomy, decisionmaking ability, and sovereign capacity
of the States. A general federal power to authorize private suits for money damages
would also strain States' ability to govern in accordance with their citizens' will,
for judgment creditors compete with other important needs and worthwhile ends for
access to the public fisc, necessitating difficult decisions involving the most sensitive
and political of judgments. A national power to remove these decisions regarding the
allocation of scarce resources from the political processes established by the citizens
of the States and commit their resolution to judicial decrees mandated by the Federal
Government and invoked by the private citizen would blur not only the State and National
Governments' distinct responsibilities but also the separate duties of the state government's
judicial and political branches.
Congress cannot abrogate States' sovereign immunity in federal court; were the rule
different here, the National Government would wield greater power in state courts
than in federal courts. This anomaly cannot be explained by reference to the state
courts' special role in the constitutional design. It would be unprecedented to infer
from the fact that Congress may declare federal law binding and enforceable in state
courts the further principle that Congress' authority to pursue federal objectives
through state courts exceeds not only its power to press other branches of the State
into its service but also its control over federal courts. The constitutional provisions
upon which this Court has relied in finding state courts peculiarly amendable to federal
command, moreover, do not distinguish those courts from the Federal Judiciary. No
constitutional precept would admit of a congressional power to require state courts
to entertain federal suits which are not within the United States' judicial power
and could not be heard in federal courts. Pp. 39-46.
3. A State's constitutional privilege to assert its sovereign immunity in its own
courts does not confer upon the State a concomitant right to disregard the Constitution
or valid federal law. States and their officers are bound by obligations imposed by
the Constitution and federal statutes that comport with the constitutional design.
Limits implicit in the constitutional principle of sovereign immunity strike the proper
balance between the supremacy of federal law and the separate sovereignty of the States.
The first limit is that sovereign immunity bars suits only in the absence of consent.
Many States have enacted statutes consenting to suits and have consented to some suits
pursuant to the plan of the Convention or to subsequent constitutional Amendments.
The second important limit is that sovereign immunity bars suits against States but
not against lesser entities, such as municipal corporations, or against state officers
for injunctive or declaratory relief or for money damages when sued in their individual
capacities. Pp. 46-48.
4. Maine has not waived its immunity. It adheres to the general rule that a specific
legislative enactment is required to waive sovereign immunity. Although petitioners
contend that Maine discriminated against federal rights by claiming immunity from
this suit, there is no evidence that it has manipulated its immunity in a systematic
fashion to discriminate against federal causes of action. To the extent Maine has
chosen to consent to certain classes of suits while maintaining its immunity from
others, it has done no more than exercise a privilege of sovereignty. P. 49.
715 A. 2d 172, affirmed.
Kennedy, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which Rehnquist, C. J., and O'Connor,
Scalia, and Thomas, JJ., joined. Souter, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which
Stevens, Ginsburg, and Breyer, JJ., joined.
JOHN H. ALDEN, et al. , PETITIONERS v. MAINE
on writ of certiorari to the supreme judicial court of maine
[June 23, 1999]
Justice Kennedy delivered the opinion of the Court.
In 1992, petitioners, a group of probation officers, filed suit against their employer,
the State of Maine, in the United States District Court for the District of Maine.
The officers alleged the State had violated the overtime provisions of the Fair Labor
Standards Act of 1938 (FLSA), 52 Stat. 1060, as amended, 29 U. S. C. §201 et seq.,
and sought compensation and liquidated damages. While the suit was pending, this Court
decided Seminole Tribe of Fla. v. Florida, 517 U. S. 44 (1996), which made it clear
that Congress lacks power under Article I to abrogate the States' sovereign immunity
from suits commenced or prosecuted in the federal courts. Upon consideration of Seminole
Tribe, the District Court dismissed petitioners' action, and the Court of Appeals
affirmed. Mills v. Maine, 118 F. 3d 37 (CA1 1997). Petitioners then filed the same
action in state court. The state trial court dismissed the suit on the basis of sovereign
immunity, and the Maine Supreme Judicial Court affirmed. 715 A. 2d 172 (1998).
The Maine Supreme Judicial Court's decision conflicts with the decision of the Supreme
Court of Arkansas, Jacoby v. Arkansas Dept. of Ed. , 331 Ark. 508, 962 S. W. 2d 773
(1998), and calls into question the constitutionality of the provisions of the FLSA
purporting to authorize private actions against States in their own courts without
regard for consent, see 29 U. S. C. §§216(b), 203(x). In light of the importance of
the question presented and the conflict between the courts, we granted certiorari.
525 U. S. ___ (1998). The United States intervened as a petitioner to defend the statute.
We hold that the powers delegated to Congress under Article I of the United States
Constitution do not include the power to subject nonconsenting States to private suits
for damages in state courts. We decide as well that the State of Maine has not consented
to suits for overtime pay and liquidated damages under the FLSA. On these premises
we affirm the judgment sustaining dismissal of the suit.
I
The Eleventh Amendment makes explicit reference to the States' immunity from suits
"commenced or prosecuted against one of the United States by Citizens of another State,
or by Citizens or Subjects of any Foreign State." U. S. Const., Amdt. 11. We have,
as a result, sometimes referred to the States' immunity from suit as "Eleventh Amendment
immunity." The phrase is convenient shorthand but something of a misnomer, for the
sovereign immunity of the States neither derives from nor is limited by the terms
of the Eleventh Amendment. Rather, as the Constitution's structure, and its history,
and the authoritative interpretations by this Court make clear, the States' immunity
from suit is a fundamental aspect of the sovereignty which the States enjoyed before
the ratification of the Constitution, and which they retain today (either literally
or by virtue of their admission into the Union upon an equal footing with the other
States) except as altered by the plan of the Convention or certain constitutional
Amendments.
A
Although the Constitution establishes a National Government with broad, often plenary
authority over matters within its recognized competence, the founding document "specifically
recognizes the States as sovereign entities." Seminole Tribe of Fla. v. Florida, supra,
at 71, n. 15; accord, Blatchford v. Native Village of Noatak, 501 U. S. 775, 779 (1991)
("[T]he States entered the federal system with their sovereignty intact"). Various
textual provisions of the Constitution assume the States' continued existence and
active participation in the fundamental processes of governance. See Printz v. United
States, 521 U. S. 898, 919 (1997) (citing Art. III, §2; Art. IV, §§2-4; Art. V). The
limited and enumerated powers granted to the Legislative, Executive, and Judicial
Branches of the National Government, moreover, underscore the vital role reserved
to the States by the constitutional design, see, e.g., Art. I, §8; Art. II, §§2-3;
Art. III, §2. Any doubt regarding the constitutional role of the States as sovereign
entities is removed by the Tenth Amendment, which, like the other provisions of the
Bill of Rights, was enacted to allay lingering concerns about the extent of the national
power. The Amendment confirms the promise implicit in the original document: "The
powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it
to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people." U. S. Const.,
Amdt. 10; see also Printz, supra, at 919; New York v. United States, 505 U. S. 144,
156-159 , 177 (1992).
The federal system established by our Constitution preserves the sovereign status
of the States in two ways. First, it reserves to them a substantial portion of the
Nation's primary sovereignty, together with the dignity and essential attributes inhering
in that status. The States "form distinct and independent portions of the supremacy,
no more subject, within their respective spheres, to the general authority than the
general authority is subject to them, within its own sphere." The Federalist No. 39,
p. 245 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961) (J. Madison).
Second, even as to matters within the competence of the National Government, the
constitutional design secures the founding generation's rejection of "the concept
of a central government that would act upon and through the States" in favor of "a
system in which the State and Federal Governments would exercise concurrent authority
over the people--who were, in Hamilton's words, `the only proper objects of government.'
" Printz, supra, at 919-920 (quoting The Federalist No. 15, at 109); accord, New York,
supra, at 166 ("The Framers explicitly chose a Constitution that confers upon Congress
the power to regulate individuals, not States"). In this the founders achieved a deliberate
departure from the Articles of Confederation: Experience under the Articles had "exploded
on all hands" the "practicality of making laws, with coercive sanctions, for the States
as political bodies." 2 Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, p. 9 (M. Farrand
ed. 1911) (J. Madison); accord, The Federalist No. 20, at 138 (J. Madison & A. Hamilton);
3 Annals of America 249 (1976) (J. Iredell).
The States thus retain "a residuary and inviolable sovereignty." The Federalist No.
39, at 245. They are not relegated to the role of mere provinces or political corporations,
but retain the dignity, though not the full authority, of sovereignty.
B
The generation that designed and adopted our federal system considered immunity from
private suits central to sovereign dignity. When the Constitution was ratified, it
was well established in English law that the Crown could not be sued without consent
in its own courts. See Chisholm v. Georgia, 2 Dall. 419, 437-446 (1793) (Iredell,
J., dissenting) (surveying English practice); cf. Nevada v. Hall, 440 U. S. 410, 414
(1979) ("The immunity of a truly independent sovereign from suit in its own courts
has been enjoyed as a matter of absolute right for centuries. Only the sovereign's
own consent could qualify the absolute character of that immunity"). In reciting the
prerogatives of the Crown, Blackstone--whose works constituted the preeminent authority
on English law for the founding generation--underscored the close and necessary relationship
understood to exist between sovereignty and immunity from suit:
"And, first, the law ascribes to the king the attribute of sovereignty, or pre-eminence...
. Hence it is, that no suit or action can be brought against the king, even in civil
matters, because no court can have jurisdiction over him. For all jurisdiction implies
superiority of power... ." 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 234-235
(1765).
Although the American people had rejected other aspects of English political theory,
the doctrine that a sovereign could not be sued without its consent was universal
in the States when the Constitution was drafted and ratified. See Chisholm, supra,
at 434-435 (Iredell, J., dissenting) ("I believe there is no doubt that neither in
the State now in question, nor in any other in the Union, any particular Legislative
mode, authorizing a compulsory suit for the recovery of money against a State, was
in being either when the Constitution was adopted, or at the time the judicial act
was passed"); Hans v. Louisiana, 134 U. S. 1, 16 (1890) ("The suability of a State,
without its consent, was a thing unknown to the law. This has been so often laid down
and acknowledged by courts and jurists that it is hardly necessary to be formally
asserted").
The ratification debates, furthermore, underscored the importance of the States'
sovereign immunity to the American people. Grave concerns were raised by the provisions
of Article III which extended the federal judicial power to controversies between
States and citizens of other States or foreign nations. As we have explained:
"Unquestionably the doctrine of sovereign immunity was a matter of importance in
the early days of independence. Many of the States were heavily indebted as a result
of the Revolutionary War. They were vitally interested in the question whether the
creation of a new federal sovereign, with courts of its own, would automatically subject
them, like lower English lords, to suits in the courts of the `higher' sovereign."
Hall, supra, at 418 (footnote omitted).
The leading advocates of the Constitution assured the people in no uncertain terms
that the Constitution would not strip the States of sovereign immunity. One assurance
was contained in The Federalist No. 81, written by Alexander Hamilton:
"It is inherent in the nature of sovereignty not to be amenable to the suit of an
individual without its consent . This is the general sense, and the general practice
of mankind; and the exemption, as one of the attributes of sovereignty, is now enjoyed
by the government of every State in the Union. Unless therefore, there is a surrender
of this immunity in the plan of the convention, it will remain with the States, and
the danger intimated must be merely ideal... . [T]here is no color to pretend that
the State governments would, by the adoption of that plan, be divested of the privilege
of paying their own debts in their own way, free from every constraint but that which
flows from the obligations of good faith. The contracts between a nation and individuals
are only binding on the conscience of the sovereign, and have no pretensions to a
compulsive force. They confer no right of action independent of the sovereign Will.
To what purpose would it be to authorize suits against States for the debts they owe?
How could recoveries be enforced? It is evident that it could not be done without
waging war against the contracting State; and to ascribe to the federal courts, by
mere implication, and in destruction of the preexisting right of the State governments,
a power which would involve such a consequence, would be altogether forced and unwarrantable."
Id., at 487-488 (emphasis in original).
At the Virginia ratifying convention, James Madison echoed this theme:
"Its jurisdiction in controversies between a state and citizens of another state
is much objected to, and perhaps without reason. It is not in the power of individuals
to call any state into court... .
"... It appears to me that this [clause] can have no operation but this--to give
a citizen a right to be heard in the federal courts, and if a state should condescend
to be a party, this court may take cognizance of it." 3 J. Elliot, Debates on the
Federal Constitution 533 (2d ed. 1854) (hereinafter Elliot's Debates).
When Madison's explanation was questioned, John Marshall provided immediate support:
"With respect to disputes between a state and the citizens of another state, its
jurisdiction has been decried with unusual vehemence. I hope no Gentleman will think
that a state will be called at the bar of the federal court. Is there no such case
at present? Are there not many cases in which the Legislature of Virginia is a party,
and yet the State is not sued? It is not rational to suppose, that the sovereign power
shall be dragged before a court. The intent is, to enable states to recover claims
of individuals residing in other states. I contend this construction is warranted
by the words. But, say they, there will be partiality in it if a State cannot be defendant
... It is necessary to be so, and cannot be avoided. I see a difficulty in making
a state defendant, which does not prevent its being plaintiff." 3 id., at 555.
Although the state conventions which addressed the issue of sovereign immunity in
their formal ratification documents sought to clarify the point by constitutional
amendment, they made clear that they, like Hamilton, Madison, and Marshall, understood
the Constitution as drafted to preserve the States' immunity from private suits. The
Rhode Island Convention thus proclaimed that "[i]t is declared by the Convention,
that the judicial power of the United States, in cases in which a state may be a party,
does not extend to criminal prosecutions, or to authorize any suit by any person against
a state." 1 id., at 336. The convention sought, in addition, an express amendment
"to remove all doubts or controversies respecting the same." Ibid. In a similar fashion,
the New York Convention "declare[d] and ma[d]e known," 1 id., at 327, its understanding
"[t]hat the judicial power of the United States, in cases in which a state may be
a party, does not extend to criminal prosecutions, or to authorize any suit by any
person against a state," 1 id., at 329. The convention proceeded to ratify the Constitution
"[u]nder these impressions, and declaring that the rights aforesaid cannot be abridged
or violated, and that the explanations aforesaid are consistent with the said Constitution,
and in confidence that the amendments which shall have been proposed to the said Constitution
will receive an early and mature consideration." Ibid.
Despite the persuasive assurances of the Constitution's leading advocates and the
expressed understanding of the only state conventions to address the issue in explicit
terms, this Court held, just five years after the Constitution was adopted, that Article
III authorized a private citizen of another State to sue the State of Georgia without
its consent. Chisholm v. Georgia, 2 Dall. 419 (1793). Each of the four Justices who
concurred in the judgment issued a separate opinion. The common theme of the opinions
was that the case fell within the literal text of Article III, which by its terms
granted jurisdiction over controversies "between a State and Citizens of another State,"
and "between a State, or the Citizens thereof, and foreign States, Citizens, or Subjects."
U. S. Const., Art. III, §2. The argument that this provision granted jurisdiction
only over cases in which the State was a plaintiff was dismissed as inconsistent with
the ordinary meaning of "between," and with the provision extending jurisdiction to
"Controversies between two or more States," which by necessity contemplated jurisdiction
over suits to which States were defendants. Two Justices also argued that sovereign
immunity was inconsistent with the principle of popular sovereignty established by
the Constitution, see 2 Dall., at 454-458 (Wilson, J.); id., at 470-472 (Jay, C. J.);
although the others did not go so far, they contended that the text of Article III
evidenced the States' surrender of sovereign immunity as to those provisions extending
jurisdiction over suits to which States were parties, see id., at 452 (Blair, J.);
id., at 468 (Cushing, J.).
Justice Iredell dissented, relying on American history, id., at 434-435, English
history, id., at 437-446, and the principles of enumerated powers and separate sovereignty,
id., at 435-436, 448, 449-450. See generally Hans, 134 U. S., at 12 ("The other justices
were more swayed by a close observance of the letter of the Constitution, without
regard to former experience and usage ... . Justice Iredell, on the contrary, contended
that it was not the intention to create new and unheard of remedies, by subjecting
sovereign States to actions at the suit of individuals, (which he conclusively showed
was never done before,) but only ... to invest the federal courts with jurisdiction
to hear and determine controversies and cases, between the parties designated, that
were properly susceptible of litigation in courts").
The Court's decision "fell upon the country with a profound shock." 1 C. Warren,
The Supreme Court in United States History 96 (rev. ed. 1926); accord, Hans, supra,
at 11; Principality of Monaco v. Mississippi, 292 U. S. 313, 325 (1934); Seminole
Tribe, 517 U. S., at 69 . "Newspapers representing a rainbow of opinion protested
what they viewed as an unexpected blow to state sovereignty. Others spoke more concretely
of prospective raids on state treasuries." D. Currie, The Constitution in Congress:
The Federalist Period 1789-1801, p. 196 (1997).
The States, in particular, responded with outrage to the decision. The Massachusetts
Legislature, for example, denounced the decision as "repugnant to the first principles
of a federal government," and called upon the State's Senators and Representatives
to take all necessary steps to "remove any clause or article of the Constitution,
which can be construed to imply or justify a decision, that, a State is compellable
to answer in any suit by an individual or individuals in any Court of the United States."
15 Papers of Alexander Hamilton 314 (H. Syrett & J. Cooke eds. 1969). Georgia's response
was more intemperate: Its House of Representatives passed a bill providing that anyone
attempting to enforce the Chisholm decision would be " `guilty of felony and shall
suffer death, without benefit of clergy, by being hanged.' " Currie, supra, at 196.
An initial proposal to amend the Constitution was introduced in the House of Representatives
the day after Chisholm was announced; the proposal adopted as the Eleventh Amendment
was introduced in the Senate promptly following an intervening recess. Currie, supra,
at 196. Congress turned to the latter proposal with great dispatch; little more than
two months after its introduction it had been endorsed by both Houses and forwarded
to the States. 4 Annals of Congress 25, 30, 477, 499 (1794); 1 Stat. 402.
Each House spent but a single day discussing the Amendment, and the vote in each
House was close to unanimous. See 4 Annals, at 30-31, 476-478 (the Senate divided
23 to 2; the House 81 to 9). All attempts to weaken the Amendment were defeated. Congress
in succession rejected proposals to limit the Amendment to suits in which "the cause
of action shall have arisen before the ratification of the amendment," or even to
cases " `[W]here such State shall have previously made provision in their own Courts,
whereby such suit may be prosecuted to effect' "; it refused as well to make an exception
for " `cases arising under treaties made under the authority of the United States.'
" 4 id., 30, 476.
It might be argued that the Chisholm decision was a correct interpretation of the
constitutional design and that the Eleventh Amendment represented a deviation from
the original understanding. This, however, seems unsupportable. First, despite the
opinion of Justice Iredell, the majority failed to address either the practice or
the understanding that prevailed in the States at the time the Constitution was adopted.
Second, even a casual reading of the opinions suggests the majority suspected the
decision would be unpopular and surprising. See, e.g., 2 Dall., at 454-455 (Wilson,
J.) (condemning the prevailing conception of sovereignty); id., at 468 (Cushing, J.)
("If the Constitution is found inconvenient in practice in this or any other particular,
it is well that a regular mode is pointed out for amendment"); id., at 478-479 (Jay,
C. J.) ("[T]here is reason to hope that the people of [Georgia] will yet perceive
that [sovereign immunity] would not have been consistent with [republican] equality");
cf. id., at 419-420 (attorney for Chisholm) ("I did not want the remonstrance of Georgia,
to satisfy me, that the motion, which I have made is unpopular. Before that remonstrance
was read, I had learnt from the acts of another State, whose will must be always dear
to me, that she too condemned it"). Finally, two Members of the majority acknowledged
that the United States might well remain immune from suit despite Article III's grant
of jurisdiction over "Controversies to which the United States shall be a Party,"
see id., at 469 (Cushing, J.); id., at 478 (Jay, C. J.), and, invoking the example
of actions to collect debts incurred before the Constitution was adopted, one raised
the possibility of "exceptions," suggesting the rule of the case might not "extend
to all the demands, and to every kind of action," see id., at 479 (Jay, C. J.). These
concessions undercut the crucial premise that either the Constitution's literal text
or the principal of popular sovereignty necessarily overrode widespread practice and
opinion.
The text and history of the Eleventh Amendment also suggest that Congress acted not
to change but to restore the original constitutional design. Although earlier drafts
of the Amendment had been phrased as express limits on the judicial power granted
in Article III, see, e.g., 3 Annals of Congress 651-652 (1793) ("The Judicial Power
of the United States shall not extend to any suits in law or equity, commenced or
prosecuted against one of the United States ..."), the adopted text addressed the
proper interpretation of that provision of the original Constitution, see U. S. Const.,
Amdt. 11 ("The Judicial Power of the United States shall not be construed to extend
to any suit in law or equity, commenced or prosecuted against one of the United States
..."). By its terms, then, the Eleventh Amendment did not redefine the federal judicial
power but instead overruled the Court:
"This amendment, expressing the will of the ultimate sovereignty of the whole country,
superior to all legislatures and all courts, actually reversed the decision of the
Supreme Court. It did not in terms prohibit suits by individuals against the States,
but declared that the Constitution should not be construed to import any power to
authorize the bringing of such suits. ... The supreme court had construed the judicial
power as extending to such a suit, and its decision was thus overruled." Hans, 134
U. S., at 11 .
The text reflects the historical context and the congressional objective in endorsing
the Amendment for ratification. Congress chose not to enact language codifying the
traditional understanding of sovereign immunity but rather to address the specific
provisions of the Constitution that had raised concerns during the ratification debates
and formed the basis of the Chisholm decision. Cf. 15 Papers of Alexander Hamilton,
at 314 (quoted supra, at 10). Given the outraged reaction to Chisholm , as well as
Congress' repeated refusal to otherwise qualify the text of the Amendment, it is doubtful
that if Congress meant to write a new immunity into the Constitution it would have
limited that immunity to the narrow text of the Eleventh Amendment:
"Can we suppose that, when the Eleventh Amendment was adopted, it was understood
to be left open for citizens of a State to sue their own state in federal courts,
whilst the idea of suits by citizens of other states, or of foreign states, was indignantly
repelled? Suppose that Congress, when proposing the Eleventh Amendment, had appended
to it a proviso that nothing therein contained should prevent a State from being sued
by its own citizens in cases arising under the Constitution or laws of the United
States, can we imagine that it would have been adopted by the States? The supposition
that it would is almost an absurdity on its face." Hans, supra, at 14-15.
The more natural inference is that the Constitution was understood, in light of its
history and structure, to preserve the States' traditional immunity from private suits.
As the Amendment clarified the only provisions of the Constitution that anyone had
suggested might support a contrary understanding, there was no reason to draft with
a broader brush.
Finally, the swiftness and near unanimity with which the Eleventh Amendment was adopted
suggest "either that the Court had not captured the original understanding, or that
the country had changed its collective mind most rapidly." D. Currie, The Constitution
in the Supreme Court: The First Century 18, n. 101 (1985). The more reasonable interpretation,
of course, is that regardless of the views of four Justices in Chisholm, the country
as a whole--which had adopted the Constitution just five years earlier--had not understood
the document to strip the States' of their immunity from private suits. Cf. Currie,
The Constitution in Congress, at 196 ("It is plain that just about everybody in Congress
agreed the Supreme Court had misread the Constitution").
Although the dissent attempts to rewrite history to reflect a different original
understanding, its evidence is unpersuasive. The handful of state statutory and constitutional
provisions authorizing suits or petitions of right against States only confirms the
prevalence of the traditional understanding that a State could not be sued in the
absence of an express waiver, for if the understanding were otherwise, the provisions
would have been unnecessary. The constitutional amendments proposed by the New York
and Rhode Island Conventions undercut rather than support the dissent's view of history,
see supra, at 8, and the amendments proposed by the Virginia and North Carolina Conventions
do not cast light upon the original understanding of the States' immunity to suit.
It is true that, in the course of all but eliminating federal-question and diversity
jurisdiction, see 3 Elliot's Debates, at 660-661 (amendment proposed by the Virginia
Convention limiting the federal-question jurisdiction to suits arising under treaties
and the diversity jurisdiction to suits between parties claiming lands under grants
from different states); 4 id., at 246 (identical amendment proposed by the North Carolina
Convention), the amendments would have removed the language in the Constitution relied
upon by the Chisholm Court. While the amendments do reflect dissatisfaction with the
scope of federal jurisdiction as a general matter, there is no evidence that they
were directed toward the question of sovereign immunity or that they reflect an understanding
that the States would be subject to private suits without consent under Article III
as drafted.
The dissent's remaining evidence cannot bear the weight the dissent seeks to place
on it. The views voiced during the ratification debates by Edmund Randolph and James
Wilson, when reiterated by the same individuals in their respective capacities as
advocate and Justice in Chisholm , were decisively rejected by the Eleventh Amendment,
and General Pinkney did not speak to the issue of sovereign immunity at all. Furthermore,
Randolph appears to have recognized that his views were in tension with the traditional
understanding of sovereign immunity, see 3 Elliot's Debates, at 573 ("I think, whatever
the law of nations may say, that any doubt respecting the construction that a state
may be plaintiff, and not defendant, is taken away by the words where a state shall
be a party "), and Wilson and Pinkney expressed a radical nationalist vision of the
constitutional design that not only deviated from the views that prevailed at the
time but, despite the dissent's apparent embrace of the position, remains startling
even today, see post, at 18 (quoting with approval Wilson's statement that " `the
government of each state ought to be subordinate to the government of the United States'
"). Nor do the controversial early suits prosecuted against Maryland and New York
reflect a widespread understanding that the States had surrendered their immunity
to suit. Maryland's decision to submit to process in Vanstophorst v. Maryland, 2 Dall.
401 (1791), aroused great controversy, see Marcus & Wexler, Suits Against States:
Diversity of Opinion In The 1790s, 1993 J. Sup. Ct. History 73, 74-75, and did not
go unnoticed by the Supreme Court, see Chisholm, 2 Dall., at 429-430 (Iredell, J.,
dissenting). In Oswald v. New York, the State refused to respond to the plaintiff's
summons until after the decision in Chisholm had been announced; even then it at first
asserted the defense that it was "a free, sovereign and independent State," and could
not be "drawn or compelled" to defend the suit. Marcus & Wexler, supra, at 76-77 (internal
quotation marks omitted). And, though the Court's decision in Chisholm may have had
"champions `every bit as vigorous in defending their interpretation of the Constitution
as were those partisans on the other side of the issue' " post, at 37, the vote on
the Eleventh Amendment makes clear that they were decidedly less numerous. See supra,
at 11.
In short, the scanty and equivocal evidence offered by the dissent establishes no
more than what is evident from the decision in Chisholm --that some members of the
founding generation disagreed with Hamilton, Madison, Marshall, Iredell, and the only
state conventions formally to address the matter. The events leading to the adoption
of the Eleventh Amendment, however, make clear that the individuals who believed the
Constitution stripped the States of their immunity from suit were at most a small
minority.
Not only do the ratification debates and the events leading to the adoption of the
Eleventh Amendment reveal the original understanding of the States' constitutional
immunity from suit, they also underscore the importance of sovereign immunity to the
founding generation. Simply put, "The Constitution never would have been ratified
if the States and their courts were to be stripped of their sovereign authority except
as expressly provided by the Constitution itself." Atascadero State Hospital v. Scanlon,
473 U. S. 234, 239 , n. 2 (1985); accord, Edelman v. Jordan, 415 U. S. 651, 660 (1974).
C
The Court has been consistent in interpreting the adoption of the Eleventh Amendment
as conclusive evidence "that the decision in Chisholm was contrary to the well-understood
meaning of the Constitution," Seminole Tribe, 517 U. S., at 69 , and that the views
expressed by Hamilton, Madison, and Marshall during the ratification debates, and
by Justice Iredell in his dissenting opinion in Chisholm, reflect the original understanding
of the Constitution. See, e.g., Hans, supra, at 12, 14-15, 18-19; Principality of
Monaco, 292 U. S., at 325 ; Edelman, supra, at 660, n. 9; Seminole Tribe, supra, at
70, and nn. 12-13. In accordance with this understanding, we have recognized a "presumption
that no anomalous and unheard-of proceedings or suits were intended to be raised up
by the Constitution--anomalous and unheard of when the constitution was adopted."
Hans, 134 U. S., at 18 ; accord, id., at 15. As a consequence, we have looked to "history
and experience, and the established order of things," id., at 14, rather than "[a]dhering
to the mere letter" of the Eleventh Amendment, id., at 13, in determining the scope
of the States' constitutional immunity from suit.
Following this approach, the Court has upheld States' assertions of sovereign immunity
in various contexts falling outside the literal text of the Eleventh Amendment. In
Hans v. Louisiana, the Court held that sovereign immunity barred a citizen from suing
his own State under the federal-question head of jurisdiction. The Court was unmoved
by the petitioner's argument that the Eleventh Amendment, by its terms, applied only
to suits brought by citizens of other States:
"It seems to us that these views of those great advocates and defenders of the Constitution
were most sensible and just, and they apply equally to the present case as to that
then under discussion. The letter is appealed to now, as it was then, as a ground
for sustaining a suit brought by an individual against a State. The reason against
it is as strong in this case as it was in that. It is an attempt to strain the Constitution
and the law to a construction never imagined or dreamed of." 134 U. S., at 14 -15.
Later decisions rejected similar requests to conform the principle of sovereign immunity
to the strict language of the Eleventh Amendment in holding that nonconsenting States
are immune from suits brought by federal corporations, Smith v. Reeves, 178 U. S.
436 (1900), foreign nations, Principality of Monaco, supra, or Indian tribes, Blatchford
v. Native Village of Noatak, 501 U. S. 775 (1991), and in concluding that sovereign
immunity is a defense to suits in admiralty, though the text of the Eleventh Amendment
addresses only suits "in law or equity," Ex parte New York, 256 U. S. 490 (1921).
These holdings reflect a settled doctrinal understanding, consistent with the views
of the leading advocates of the Constitution's ratification, that sovereign immunity
derives not from the Eleventh Amendment but from the structure of the original Constitution
itself. See, e.g., Idaho v. Coeur d'Alene Tribe of Idaho, 521 U. S. 261, 267-268 (1997)
(acknowledging "the broader concept of immunity, implicit in the Constitution, which
we have regarded the Eleventh Amendment as evidencing and exemplifying"); Seminole
Tribe, supra, at 55-56; Pennhurst State School and Hospital v. Halderman, 465 U. S.
89, 98-99 (1984); Ex parte New York, supra, at 497. The Eleventh Amendment confirmed
rather than established sovereign immunity as a constitutional principle; it follows
that the scope of the States' immunity from suit is demarcated not by the text of
the Amendment alone but by fundamental postulates implicit in the constitutional design.
As we explained in Principality of Monaco:
"Manifestly, we cannot rest with a mere literal application of the words of §2 of
Article III, or assume that the letter of the Eleventh Amendment exhausts the restrictions
upon suits against non-consenting States. Behind the words of the constitutional provisions
are postulates which limit and control. There is the essential postulate that the
controversies, as contemplated, shall be found to be of a justiciable character. There
is also the postulate that States of the Union, still possessing attributes of sovereignty,
shall be immune from suits, without their consent, save where there has been `a surrender
of this immunity
in the plan of the convention.' " 292 U. S., at 322 -
323 (quoting The Federalist No. 81, at 487) (footnote omitted).
Or, as we have more recently reaffirmed:
"Although the text of the Amendment would appear to restrict only the Article III
diversity jurisdiction of the federal courts, `we have understood the Eleventh Amendment
to stand not so much for what it says, but for the presupposition ... which it confirms.'
Blatchford v. Native Village of Noatak, [ supra, at 779]. That presupposition, first
observed over a century ago in Hans v. Louisiana, [supra], has two parts: first, that
each State is a sovereign entity in our federal system; and second, that ` "[i]t is
inherent in the nature of sovereignty not to be amenable to the suit of an individual
without its consent," ' id., at 13 (emphasis deleted), quoting The Federalist No.
81, p. 487 ..." Seminole Tribe, supra, at 54.
Accord, Puerto Rico Aqueduct and Sewer Authority v. Metcalf & Eddy, Inc., 506 U.
S. 139, 146 (1993) ("The Amendment is rooted in a recognition that the States, although
a union, maintain certain attributes of sovereignty, including sovereign immunity").
II
In this case we must determine whether Congress has the power, under Article I, to
subject nonconsenting States to private suits in their own courts. As the foregoing
discussion makes clear, the fact that the Eleventh Amendment by its terms limits only
"[t]he Judicial power of the United States" does not resolve the question. To rest
on the words of the Amendment alone would be to engage in the type of ahistorical
literalism we have rejected in interpreting the scope of the States' sovereign immunity
since the discredited decision in Chisholm . Seminole Tribe, 517 U. S., at 68 ; see
also id., at 69 (quoting Principality of Monaco, supra, at 326, and Hans, 134 U. S.,
at 15 ) ("[W]e long have recognized that blind reliance upon the text of the Eleventh
Amendment is `to strain the Constitution and the law to a construction never imagined
or dreamed of ' ").
While the constitutional principle of sovereign immunity does pose a bar to federal
jurisdiction over suits against nonconsenting States, see, e.g., Principality of Monaco,
292 U. S., at 322 -323, this is not the only structural basis of sovereign immunity
implicit in the constitutional design. Rather, "[t]here is also the postulate that
States of the Union, still possessing attributes of sovereignty, shall be immune from
suits, without their consent, save where there has been `a surrender of this immunity
in the plan of the convention.' " Ibid. (quoting The Federalist No. 81, at 487); accord,
Blatchford, supra, at 781; Seminole Tribe, supra, at 68. This separate and distinct
structural principle is not directly related to the scope of the judicial power established
by Article III, but inheres in the system of federalism established by the Constitution.
In exercising its Article I powers Congress may subject the States to private suits
in their own courts only if there is "compelling evidence" that the States were required
to surrender this power to Congress pursuant to the constitutional design. Blatchford,
501 U. S., at 781 .
A
Petitioners contend the text of the Constitution and our recent sovereign immunity
decisions establish that the States were required to relinquish this portion of their
sovereignty. We turn first to these sources.
1
Article I, §8 grants Congress broad power to enact legislation in several enumerated
areas of national concern. The Supremacy Clause, furthermore, provides:
"This Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be made in Pursuance
thereof ... , shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State
shall be bound thereby, any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any state to the
Contrary notwithstanding." U. S. Const., Art. VI.
It is contended that, by virtue of these provisions, where Congress enacts legislation
subjecting the States to suit, the legislation by necessity overrides the sovereign
immunity of the States.
As is evident from its text, however, the Supremacy Clause enshrines as "the supreme
Law of the Land" only those federal Acts that accord with the constitutional design.
See Printz, 521 U. S., at 924 . Appeal to the Supremacy Clause alone merely raises
the question whether a law is a valid exercise of the national power. See The Federalist
No. 33, at 204 (A. Hamilton) ("But it will not follow from this doctrine that acts
of the larger society which are not pursuant to its constitutional powers, but which
are invasions of the residuary authorities of the smaller societies, will become the
supreme law of the land"); Printz, supra, at 924-925.
The Constitution, by delegating to Congress the power to establish the supreme law
of the land when acting within its enumerated powers, does not foreclose a State from
asserting immunity to claims arising under federal law merely because that law derives
not from the State itself but from the national power. A contrary view could not be
reconciled with Hans v. Louisiana, supra, which sustained Louisiana's immunity in
a private suit arising under the Constitution itself; with Employees of Dept. of Public
Health and Welfare of Mo. v. Department of Public Health and Welfare of Mo., 411 U.
S. 279, 283 (1973), which recognized that the FLSA was binding upon Missouri but nevertheless
upheld the State's immunity to a private suit to recover under that Act; or with numerous
other decisions to the same effect. We reject any contention that substantive federal
law by its own force necessarily overrides the sovereign immunity of the States. When
a State asserts its immunity to suit, the question is not the primacy of federal law
but the implementation of the law in a manner consistent with the constitutional sovereignty
of the States.
Nor can we conclude that the specific Article I powers delegated to Congress necessarily
include, by virtue of the Necessary and Proper Clause or otherwise, the incidental
authority to subject the States to private suits as a means of achieving objectives
otherwise within the scope of the enumerated powers. Although some of our decisions
had endorsed this contention, see Parden v. Terminal R. Co. of Ala. Docks Dept., 377
U. S. 184, 190-194 (1964); Pennsylvania v. Union Gas Co., 491 U. S. 1, 13-23 (1989)
(plurality opinion), they have since been overruled, see Seminole Tribe, supra, at
63-67, 72; College Savings Bank v. Florida Prepaid Postsecondary Ed. Expense Bd.,
ante, p. ____ . As we have recognized in an analogous context:
"When a `La[w] ... for carrying into Execution' the Commerce Clause violates the
principle of state sovereignty reflected in the various constitutional provisions
... it is not a `La[w] ... proper for carrying into Execution the Commerce Clause,'
and is thus, in the words of The Federalist, `merely [an] ac[t] of usurpation' which
`deserve[s] to be treated as such.' " Printz, supra, at 923-924 (quoting The Federalist
No. 33, at 204 (A. Hamilton)) (ellipses and alterations in Printz ).
The cases we have cited, of course, came at last to the conclusion that neither the
Supremacy Clause nor the enumerated powers of Congress confer authority to abrogate
the States' immunity from suit in federal court. The logic of the decisions, however,
does not turn on the forum in which the suits were prosecuted but extends to state-court
suits as well.
The dissenting opinion seeks to reopen these precedents, contending that state sovereign
immunity must derive either from the common law (in which case the dissent contends
it is defeasible by statute) or from natural law (in which case the dissent believes
it cannot bar a federal claim). See post, at 41. As should be obvious to all, this
is a false dichotomy. The text and the structure of the Constitution protect various
rights and principles. Many of these, such as the right to trial by jury and the prohibition
on unreasonable searches and seizures, derive from the common law. The common-law
lineage of these rights does not mean they are defeasible by statute or remain mere
common-law rights, however. They are, rather, constitutional rights, and form the
fundamental law of the land.
Although the sovereign immunity of the States derives at least in part from the common-law
tradition, the structure and history of the Constitution make clear that the immunity
exists today by constitutional design. The dissent has provided no persuasive evidence
that the founding generation regarded the States' sovereign immunity as defeasible
by federal statute. While the dissent implies this view was held by Madison and Marshall,
see post, at 20, nothing in the comments made by either individual at the ratification
conventions states, or even implies, such an understanding. Although the dissent seizes
upon Justice Iredell's statutory analysis in Chisholm in attempt to attribute this
view to Justice Iredell, see post, at 30-31, citing Chisholm, 2 Dall., at 449 (Iredell,
J., dissenting), Justice Iredell's views on the underlying constitutional question
are clear enough from other portions of his dissenting opinion:
"So much, however, has been said on the Constitution, that it may not be improper
to intimate that my present opinion is strongly against any construction of it, which
will admit, under any circumstances, a compulsive suit against a State for the recovery
of money. I think every word in the Constitution may have its full effect without
involving this consequence, and that nothing but express words, or an insurmountable
implication (neither of which I consider, can be found in this case) would authorize
the deduction of so high a power." Id., at 449-450.
Despite the dissent's assertion to the contrary, the fact that a right is not defeasible
by statute means only that it is protected by the Constitution, not that it derives
from natural law. Whether the dissent's attribution of our reasoning and conclusions
to natural law results from analytical confusion or rhetorical device, it is simply
inaccurate. We do not contend the founders could not have stripped the States of sovereign
immunity and granted Congress power to subject them to private suit but only that
they did not do so. By the same token, the contours of sovereign immunity are determined
by the founders' understanding, not by the principles or limitations derived from
natural law.
The dissent has offered no evidence that the founders believed sovereign immunity
extended only to cases where the sovereign was the source of the right asserted. No
such limitation existed on sovereign immunity in England, where sovereign immunity
was predicated on a different theory altogether. See 1 F. Pollock & F. Maitland, History
of English Law 518 (2d ed. 1909), quoted in Nevada v. Hall, 440 U. S., at 415 , n.
6 (" `[The King] can not be compelled to answer in his own court, but this is true
of every petty lord of every petty manor' "); accord, 3 W. Holdsworth, A History of
English Law 465 (3d ed. 1927) ("[N]o feudal lord could be sued in his own court").
It is doubtful whether the King was regarded, in any meaningful sense, as the font
of the traditions and customs which formed the substance of the common law, yet he
could not be sued on a common-law claim in his own courts. And it strains credibility
to imagine that the King could have been sued in his own court on, say, a French cause
of action.
In light of the ratification debates and the history of the Eleventh Amendment, there
is no reason to believe the founders intended the Constitution to preserve a more
restricted immunity in the United States. On the contrary, Congress' refusal to modify
the text of the Eleventh Amendment to create an exception to sovereign immunity for
cases arising under treaties, see supra, at 11, suggests the States' sovereign immunity
was understood to extend beyond state-law causes of action. And surely the dissent
does not believe that sovereign immunity poses no bar to a state-law suit against
the United States in federal court, or that the Federal Tort Claims Act effected a
contraction, rather than an expansion, of the United States' amenability to suit.
2
There are isolated statements in some of our cases suggesting that the Eleventh Amendment
is inapplicable in state courts. See Hilton v. South Carolina Public Railways Comm'n,
502 U. S. 197, 204-205 (1991); Will v. Michigan Dept. of State Police, 491 U. S. 58,
63 (1989); Atascadero State Hospital v. Scanlon, 473 U. S., at 239 -240, n. 2; Maine
v. Thiboutot, 448 U. S. 1, 9 , n. 7 (1980); Nevada v. Hall, 440 U. S., at 418 -421.
This, of course, is a truism as to the literal terms of the Eleventh Amendment. As
we have explained, however, the bare text of the Amendment is not an exhaustive description
of the States' constitutional immunity from suit. The cases, furthermore, do not decide
the question presented here--whether the States retain immunity from private suits
in their own courts notwithstanding an attempted abrogation by the Congress.
Two of the cases discussing state-court immunity may be dismissed out of hand. The
footnote digressions in Atascadero State Hospital and Thiboutot were irrelevant to
either opinion's holding or rationale. The discussion in Will was also unnecessary
to the decision; our holding that 42 U. S. C. §1983 did not create a cause of action
against the States rendered it unnecessary to determine the scope of the States' constitutional
immunity from suit in their own courts. Our opinions in Hilton and Hall, however,
require closer attention, for in those cases we sustained suits against States in
state courts.
In Hilton we held that an injured employee of a state-owned railroad could sue his
employer (an arm of the State) in state court under the Federal Employers' Liability
Act (FELA), 53 Stat. 1404, 45 U. S. C. §§51-60. Our decision was "controlled and informed"
by stare decisis. 502 U. S., at 201. A generation earlier we had held that because
the FELA made clear that all who operated railroads would be subject to suit by injured
workers, States that chose to enter the railroad business after the statute's enactment
impliedly waived their sovereign immunity from such suits. See Parden, supra. Some
States had excluded railroad workers from the coverage of their workers' compensation
statutes on the assumption that FELA provided adequate protection for those workers.
Hilton, supra, at 202 . Closing the courts to FELA suits against state employers would
have dislodged settled expectations and required an extensive legislative response.
Ibid.
There is language in Hilton which gives some support to the position of petitioners
here but our decision did not squarely address, much less resolve, the question of
Congress' power to abrogate States' immunity from suit in their own courts. The respondent
in Hilton, the South Carolina Public Railways Commission, neither contested Congress'
constitutional authority to subject it to suits for money damages nor raised sovereign
immunity as an affirmative defense. See Brief for Respondent in No. 90-848, O. T.
1991, pp. 7, n. 14, 21. Nor was the State's litigation strategy surprising. Hilton
was litigated and decided in the wake of Union Gas, and before this Court's decisions
in New York, Printz, and Seminole Tribe . At that time it may have appeared to the
State that Congress' power to abrogate its immunity from suit in any court was not
limited by the Constitution at all, so long as Congress made its intent sufficiently
clear.
Furthermore, our decision in Parden was based on concepts of waiver and consent.
Although later decisions have undermined the basis of Parden 's reasoning, see, e.g.,
Welch v. Texas Dept. of Highways and Public Transp., 483 U. S. 468, 476-478 (1987)
(recognizing that Parden erred in finding a clear congressional intent to subject
the States to suit); College Savings Bank, ante, at ____ (overruling Parden 's theory
of constructive waiver), we have not questioned the general proposition that a State
may waive its sovereign immunity and consent to suit, see Seminole Tribe, 517 U. S.,
at 65 .
Hilton, then, must be read in light of the doctrinal basis of Parden, the issues
presented and argued by the parties, and the substantial reliance interests drawn
into question by the litigation. When so read, we believe the decision is best understood
not as recognizing a congressional power to subject nonconsenting States to private
suits in their own courts, nor even as endorsing the constructive waiver theory of
Parden, but as simply adhering, as a matter of stare decisis and presumed historical
fact, to the narrow proposition that certain States had consented to be sued by injured
workers covered by the FELA, at least in their own courts.
In Hall we considered whether California could subject Nevada to suit in California's
courts and determined the Constitution did not bar it from doing so. We noted that
"[t]he doctrine of sovereign immunity is an amalgam of two quite different concepts,
one applicable to suits in the sovereign's own courts and the other to suits in the
courts of another sovereign." 440 U. S., at 414. We acknowledged that "[t]he immunity
of a truly independent sovereign from suit in its own courts has been enjoyed as a
matter of absolute right for centuries. Only the sovereign's own consent could qualify
the absolute character of that immunity," ibid, that "the notion that immunity from
suit is an attribute of sovereignty is reflected in our cases," id., at 415, and that
"[t]his explanation adequately supports the conclusion that no sovereign may be sued
in its own courts without its consent," id., at 416. We sharply distinguished, however,
a sovereign's immunity from suit in the courts of another sovereign:
"[B]ut [this explanation] affords no support for a claim of immunity in another sovereign's
courts. Such a claim necessarily implicates the power and authority of a second sovereign;
its source must be found either in an agreement, express or implied, between the two
sovereigns, or in the voluntary decision of the second to respect the dignity of the
first as a matter of comity." Ibid.
Since we determined the Constitution did not reflect an agreement between the States
to respect the sovereign immunity of one another, California was free to determine
whether it would respect Nevada's sovereignty as a matter of comity.
Our opinion in Hall did distinguish a State's immunity from suit in federal court
from its immunity in the courts of other States; it did not, however, address or consider
any differences between a State's sovereign immunity in federal court and in its own
courts. Our reluctance to find an implied constitutional limit on the power of the
States cannot be construed, furthermore, to support an analogous reluctance to find
implied constitutional limits on the power of the Federal Government. The Constitution,
after all, treats the powers of the States differently from the powers of the Federal
Government. As we explained in Hall:
"[I]n view of the Tenth Amendment's reminder that powers not delegated to the Federal
Government nor prohibited to the States are reserved to the States or to the people,
the existence of express limitations on state sovereignty may equally imply that caution
should be exercised before concluding that unstated limitations on state power were
intended by the Framers." Id., at 425 (footnote omitted).
The Federal Government, by contrast, "can claim no powers which are not granted to
it by the constitution, and the powers actually granted must be such as are expressly
given, or given by necessary implication." Martin v. Hunter's Lessee, 1 Wheat. 304,
326 (1816); see also City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U. S. 507, 516 (1997); United States
v. Lopez, 514 U. S. 549, 552 (1995).
Our decision in Hall thus does not support the argument urged by petitioners here.
The decision addressed neither Congress' power to subject States to private suits
nor the States' immunity from suit in their own courts. In fact, the distinction drawn
between a sovereign's immunity in its own courts and its immunity in the courts of
another sovereign, as well as the reasoning on which this distinction was based, are
consistent with, and even support, the proposition urged by the respondent here--that
the Constitution reserves to the States a constitutional immunity from private suits
in their own courts which cannot be abrogated by Congress.
Petitioners seek support in two additional decisions. In Reich v. Collins, 513 U.
S. 106 (1994), we held that, despite its immunity from suit in federal court, a State
which holds out what plainly appears to be "a clear and certain" postdeprivation remedy
for taxes collected in violation of federal law may not declare, after disputed taxes
have been paid in reliance on this remedy, that the remedy does not in fact exist.
Id., at 108. This case arose in the context of tax-refund litigation, where a State
may deprive a taxpayer of all other means of challenging the validity of its tax laws
by holding out what appears to be a "clear and certain" postdeprivation remedy. Ibid.;
see also Fair Assessment in Real Estate Assn., Inc. v. McNary, 454 U. S. 100 (1981).
In this context, due process requires the State to provide the remedy it has promised.
Cf. Hudson v. Palmer, 468 U. S. 517, 539 (1984) ( O'Connor, J., concurring). The obligation
arises from the Constitution itself; Reich does not speak to the power of Congress
to subject States to suits in their own courts.
In Howlett v. Rose, 496 U. S. 356 (1990) , we held that a state court could not refuse
to hear a §1983 suit against a school board on the basis of sovereign immunity. The
school board was not an arm of the State, however, so it could not assert any constitutional
defense of sovereign immunity to which the State would have been entitled. See Mt.
Healthy City Bd. of Ed. v. Doyle, 429 U. S. 274, 280 (1977). In Howlett, then, the
only question was "whether a state-law defense of `sovereign immunity' is available
to a school board otherwise subject to suit in a Florida court even though such a
defense would not be available if the action had been brought in a federal forum."
496 U. S., at 358 -359. The decision did not address the question of Congress' power
to compel a state court to entertain an action against a nonconsenting State.
B
Whether Congress has authority under Article I to abrogate a State's immunity from
suit in its own courts is, then, a question of first impression. In determining whether
there is "compelling evidence" that this derogation of the States' sovereignty is
"inherent in the constitutional compact," Blatchford, 501 U. S., at 781 , we continue
our discussion of history, practice, precedent, and the structure of the Constitution.
1
We look first to evidence of the original understanding of the Constitution. Petitioners
contend that because the ratification debates and the events surrounding the adoption
of the Eleventh Amendment focused on the States' immunity from suit in federal courts,
the historical record gives no instruction as to the founding generation's intent
to preserve the States' immunity from suit in their own courts.
We believe, however, that the founders' silence is best explained by the simple fact
that no one, not even the Constitution's most ardent opponents, suggested the document
might strip the States of the immunity. In light of the overriding concern regarding
the States' war-time debts, together with the well known creativity, foresight, and
vivid imagination of the Constitution's opponents, the silence is most instructive.
It suggests the sovereign's right to assert immunity from suit in its own courts was
a principle so well established that no one conceived it would be altered by the new
Constitution.
The arguments raised against the Constitution confirm this strong inference. In England,
the rule was well established that "no lord could be sued by a vassal in his own court,
but each petty lord was subject to suit in the courts of a higher lord." Hall, 440
U. S., at 414 -415. It was argued that, by analogy, the States could be sued without
consent in federal court. Id., at 418. The point of the argument was that federal
jurisdiction under Article III would circumvent the States' immunity from suit in
their own courts. The argument would have made little sense if the States were understood
to have relinquished the immunity in all events.
The response the Constitution's advocates gave to the argument is also telling. Relying
on custom and practice--and, in particular, on the States' immunity from suit in their
own courts, see 3 Elliot's Debates, at 555 (Marshall)--they contended that no individual
could sue a sovereign without its consent. It is true the point was directed toward
the power of the Federal Judiciary, for that was the only question at issue. The logic
of the argument, however, applies with even greater force in the context of a suit
prosecuted against a sovereign in its own courts, for in this setting, more than any
other, sovereign immunity was long established and unquestioned. See Hall, supra,
at 414.
Similarly, while the Eleventh Amendment by its terms addresses only "the Judicial
power of the United States," nothing in Chisholm , the catalyst for the Amendment,
suggested the States were not immune from suits in their own courts. The only Justice
to address the issue, in fact, was explicit in distinguishing between sovereign immunity
in federal court and in a State's own courts. See 2 Dall., at 452 (Blair, J.) ("When
sovereigns are sued in their own Courts, such a method [a petition of right] may have
been established as the most respectful form of demand; but we are not now in a State-Court;
and if sovereignty be an exemption from suit in any other than the sovereign's own
Courts, it follows that when a State, by adopting the Constitution, has agreed to
be amenable to the judicial power of the United States, she has, in that respect,
given up her right of sovereignty").
The language of the Eleventh Amendment, furthermore, was directed toward the only
provisions of the constitutional text believed to call the States' immunity from private
suits into question. Although Article III expressly contemplated jurisdiction over
suits between States and individuals, nothing in the Article or in any other part
of the Constitution suggested the States could not assert immunity from private suit
in their own courts or that Congress had the power to abrogate sovereign immunity
there.
Finally, the Congress which endorsed the Eleventh Amendment rejected language limiting
the Amendment's scope to cases where the States had made available a remedy in their
own courts. See supra, at 11. Implicit in the proposal, it is evident, was the premise
that the States retained their immunity and the concomitant authority to decide whether
to allow private suits against the sovereign in their own courts.
In light of the language of the Constitution and the historical context, it is quite
apparent why neither the ratification debates nor the language of the Eleventh Amendment
addressed the States' immunity from suit in their own courts. The concerns voiced
at the ratifying conventions, the furor raised by Chisholm, and the speed and unanimity
with which the Amendment was adopted, moreover, underscore the jealous care with which
the founding generation sought to preserve the sovereign immunity of the States. To
read this history as permitting the inference that the Constitution stripped the States
of immunity in their own courts and allowed Congress to subject them to suit there
would turn on its head the concern of the founding generation--that Article III might
be used to circumvent state-court immunity. In light of the historical record it is
difficult to conceive that the Constitution would have been adopted if it had been
understood to strip the States of immunity from suit in their own courts and cede
to the Federal Government a power to subject nonconsenting States to private suits
in these fora.
2
Our historical analysis is supported by early congressional practice, which provides
"contemporaneous and weighty evidence of the Constitution's meaning." Printz, 521
U. S., at 905 (internal quotation marks omitted). Although early Congresses enacted
various statutes authorizing federal suits in state court, see id., at 906-907 (listing
statutes); Testa v. Katt, 330 U. S. 386, 389-390 (1947), we have discovered no instance
in which they purported to authorize suits against nonconsenting States in these fora.
The "numerousness of these statutes [authorizing suit in state court], contrasted
with the utter lack of statutes" subjecting States to suit, "suggests an assumed absence
of such power." 521 U. S., at 907-908. It thus appears early Congresses did not believe
they had the power to authorize private suits against the States in their own courts.
Not only were statutes purporting to authorize private suits against nonconsenting
States in state courts not enacted by early Congresses, statutes purporting to authorize
such suits in any forum are all but absent from our historical experience. The first
statute we confronted that even arguably purported to subject the States to private
actions was the FELA. See Parden, 377 U. S., at 187 ("Here, for the first time in
this Court, a State's claim of immunity against suit by an individual meets a suit
brought upon a cause of action expressly created by Congress"). As we later recognized,
however, even this statute did not clearly create a cause of action against the States.
See Welch, 483 U. S., at 476 -478. The provisions of the FLSA at issue here, which
were enacted in the aftermath of Parden, are among the first statutory enactments
purporting in express terms to subject nonconsenting States to private suits. Although
similar statutes have multiplied in the last generation, "they are of such recent
vintage that they are no more probative than the [FLSA] of a constitutional tradition
that lends meaning to the text. Their persuasive force is far outweighed by almost
two centuries of apparent congressional avoidance of the practice." 521 U. S., at
918 .
Even the recent statutes, moreover, do not provide evidence of an understanding that
Congress has a greater power to subject States to suit in their own courts than in
federal courts. On the contrary, the statutes purport to create causes of actions
against the States which are enforceable in federal, as well as state, court. To the
extent recent practice thus departs from longstanding tradition, it reflects not so
much an understanding that the States have surrendered their immunity from suit in
their own courts as the erroneous view, perhaps inspired by Parden and Union Gas ,
that Congress may subject nonconsenting States to private suits in any forum.
3
The theory and reasoning of our earlier cases suggest the States do retain a constitutional
immunity from suit in their own courts. We have often described the States' immunity
in sweeping terms, without reference to whether the suit was prosecuted in state or
federal court. See, e.g., Briscoe v. Bank of Kentucky, 11 Pet. 257, 321-322 (1837)
("No sovereign state is liable to be sued without her consent"); Board of Liquidation
v. McComb, 92 U. S. 531, 541 (1876) ("A State, without its consent, cannot be sued
by an individual"); In re Ayers, 123 U. S. 443 , 506 (1887) (same); Great Northern
Life Ins. Co. v. Read, 322 U. S. 47, 51 (1944) ("The inherent nature of sovereignty
prevents actions against a state by its own citizens without its consent").
We have said on many occasions, furthermore, that the States retain their immunity
from private suits prosecuted in their own courts. See, e.g., Beers v. Arkansas, 20
How. 527, 529 (1858) ("It is an established principle of jurisprudence in all civilized
nations that the sovereign cannot be sued in its own courts, or in any other, without
its consent and permission"); Railroad Co. v. Tennessee, 101 U. S. 337, 339 (1880)
("The principle is elementary that a State cannot be sued in its own courts without
its consent. This is a privilege of sovereignty"); Cunningham v. Macon & Brunswick
R. Co., 109 U. S. 446, 451 (1883) ("It may be accepted as a point of departure unquestioned,
that neither a State nor the United States can be sued as defendant in any court in
this country without their consent, except in the limited class of cases in which
a State may be made a party in the Supreme Court of the United States by virtue of
the original jurisdiction conferred on this court by the Constitution"); Louisiana
ex rel. New York Guaranty & Indemnity Co. v. Steele, 134 U. S. 230, 232 (1890) (finding
a suit against a state official in state court to be "clearly within the principle"
of the Eleventh Amendment decisions); Hess v. Port Authority Trans-Hudson Corporation,
513 U. S. 30, 39 (1994) ("The Eleventh Amendment largely shields the States from suit
in federal court without their consent, leaving the parties with claims against a
State to present them, if the State permits, in the State's own tribunals"); Seminole
Tribe, 517 U. S., at 71 , n. 14 ("[T]his Court is empowered to review a question of
federal law arising from a state court decision where a State has consented to suit");
see also Great Northern Life Ins. Co. v. Read, 322 U. S., at 59 (Frankfurter, J.,
dissenting) ("The Eleventh Amendment has put state immunity from suit into the Constitution.
Therefore, it is not in the power of individuals to bring any State into court--the
State's or that of the United States--except with its consent"); accord, id., at 51,
53 (majority opinion); cf. Quern v. Jordan, 440 U. S. 332, 440 (1979); Green v. Mansour,
474 U. S. 64, 71 (1985).
We have also relied on the States' immunity in their own courts as a premise in our
Eleventh Amendment rulings. See Hans, 134 U. S., at 10 ("It is true the amendment
does so read, and, if there were no other reason or ground for abating his suit, it
might be maintainable; and then we should have this anomalous result [that a State
may be sued by its own citizen though not by the citizen of another State, and that
a State] may be thus sued in the federal courts, although not allowing itself to be
sued in its own courts. If this is the necessary consequence of the language of the
Constitution and the law, the result is no less startling and unexpected than [ Chisholm
]"); id., at 18 ("The state courts have no power to entertain suits by individuals
against a State without its consent. Then how does the Circuit Court, having only
concurrent jurisdiction, acquire any such power?").
In particular, the exception to our sovereign immunity doctrine recognized in Ex
parte Young, 209 U. S. 123 (1908), is based in part on the premise that sovereign
immunity bars relief against States and their officers in both state and federal courts,
and that certain suits for declaratory or injunctive relief against state officers
must therefore be permitted if the Constitution is to remain the supreme law of the
land. As we explained in General Oil Co. v. Crain, 209 U. S. 211 (1908), a case decided
the same day as Ex parte Young and extending the rule of that case to state-court
suits:
" It seems to be an obvious consequence that as a State can only perform its functions
through its officers, a restraint upon them is a restraint upon its sovereignty from
which it is exempt without its consent in the state tribunals, and exempt by the Eleventh
Amendment of the Constitution of the United States, in the national tribunals. The
error is in the universality of the conclusion, as we have seen. Necessarily to give
adequate protection to constitutional rights a distinction must be made between valid
and invalid state laws, as determining the character of the suit against state officers.
And the suit at bar illustrates the necessity. If a suit against state officers is
precluded in the national courts by the Eleventh Amendment to the Constitution, and
may be forbidden by a State to its courts, as it is contended in the case at bar that
it may be, without power of review by this court, it must be evident that an easy
way is open to prevent the enforcement of many provisions of the Constitution ...
. See Ex parte Young, ante, p. 123, where this subject is fully discussed and the
cases reviewed." 209 U. S., at 226 -227.
Had we not understood the States to retain a constitutional immunity from suit in
their own courts, the need for the Ex parte Young rule would have been less pressing,
and the rule would not have formed so essential a part of our sovereign immunity doctrine.
See Idaho v. Coeur d'Alene Tribe of Idaho, 521 U. S., at 270 -271 (principal opinion).
As it is settled doctrine that neither substantive federal law nor attempted congressional
abrogation under Article I bars a State from raising a constitutional defense of sovereign
immunity in federal court, see Part II-A-1, supra, our decisions suggesting that the
States retain an analogous constitutional immunity from private suits in their own
courts support the conclusion that Congress lacks the Article I power to subject the
States to private suits in those fora.
4
Our final consideration is whether a congressional power to subject nonconsenting
States to private suits in their own courts is consistent with the structure of the
Constitution. We look both to the essential principles of federalism and to the special
role of the state courts in the constitutional design.
Although the Constitution grants broad powers to Congress, our federalism requires
that Congress treat the States in a manner consistent with their status as residuary
sovereigns and joint participants in the governance of the Nation. See, e.g., United
States v. Lopez, 514 U. S., at 583 (concurring opinion); Printz, 521 U. S., at 935
; New York, 505 U. S., at 188 . The founding generation thought it "neither becoming
nor convenient that the several States of the Union, invested with that large residuum
of sovereignty which had not been delegated to the United States, should be summoned
as defendants to answer the complaints of private persons." In re Ayers, 123 U. S.,
at 505 . The principle of sovereign immunity preserved by constitutional design "thus
accords the States the respect owed them as members of the federation." Puerto Rico
Aqueduct and Sewer Authority, 506 U. S., at 146 ; accord, Coeur d'Alene Tribe, supra,
at 268 (recognizing "the dignity and respect afforded a State, which the immunity
is designed to protect").
Petitioners contend that immunity from suit in federal court suffices to preserve
the dignity of the States. Private suits against nonconsenting States, however, present
"the indignity of subjecting a State to the coercive process of judicial tribunals
at the instance of private parties," In re Ayers, supra, at 505; accord, Seminole
Tribe, 517 U. S., at 58 , regardless of the forum. Not only must a State defend or
default but also it must face the prospect of being thrust, by federal fiat and against
its will, into the disfavored status of a debtor, subject to the power of private
citizens to levy on its treasury or perhaps even government buildings or property
which the State administers on the public's behalf.
In some ways, of course, a congressional power to authorize private suits against
nonconsenting States in their own courts would be even more offensive to state sovereignty
than a power to authorize the suits in a federal forum. Although the immunity of one
sovereign in the courts of another has often depended in part on comity or agreement,
the immunity of a sovereign in its own courts has always been understood to be within
the sole control of the sovereign itself. See generally Hall, 440 U. S., at 414 -418.
A power to press a State's own courts into federal service to coerce the other branches
of the State, furthermore, is the power first to turn the State against itself and
ultimately to commandeer the entire political machinery of the State against its will
and at the behest of individuals. Cf. Coeur d'Alene Tribe, supra, at 276. Such plenary
federal control of state governmental processes denigrates the separate sovereignty
of the States.
It is unquestioned that the Federal Government retains its own immunity from suit
not only in state tribunals but also in its own courts. In light of our constitutional
system recognizing the essential sovereignty of the States, we are reluctant to conclude
that the States are not entitled to a reciprocal privilege.
Underlying constitutional form are considerations of great substance. Private suits
against nonconsenting States--especially suits for money damages--may threaten the
financial integrity of the States. It is indisputable that, at the time of the founding,
many of the States could have been forced into insolvency but for their immunity from
private suits for money damages. Even today, an unlimited congressional power to authorize
suits in state court to levy upon the treasuries of the States for compensatory damages,
attorney's fees, and even punitive damages could create staggering burdens, giving
Congress a power and a leverage over the States that is not contemplated by our constitutional
design. The potential national power would pose a severe and notorious danger to the
States and their resources.
A congressional power to strip the States of their immunity from private suits in
their own courts would pose more subtle risks as well. "The principle of immunity
from litigation assures the states and the nation from unanticipated intervention
in the processes of government." Great Northern Life Ins. Co. v. Read, 322 U. S.,
at 53 . When the States' immunity from private suits is disregarded, "the course of
their public policy and the administration of their public affairs" may become "subject
to and controlled by the mandates of judicial tribunals without their consent, and
in favor of individual interests." In re Ayers, supra, at 505. While the States have
relinquished their immunity from suit in some special contexts--at least as a practical
matter--see Part III, infra, this surrender carries with it substantial costs to the
autonomy, the decisionmaking ability, and the sovereign capacity of the States.
A general federal power to authorize private suits for money damages would place
unwarranted strain on the States' ability to govern in accordance with the will of
their citizens. Today, as at the time of the founding, the allocation of scarce resources
among competing needs and interests lies at the heart of the political process. While
the judgment creditor of the State may have a legitimate claim for compensation, other
important needs and worthwhile ends compete for access to the public fisc. Since all
cannot be satisfied in full, it is inevitable that difficult decisions involving the
most sensitive and political of judgments must be made. If the principle of representative
government is to be preserved to the States, the balance between competing interests
must be reached after deliberation by the political process established by the citizens
of the State, not by judicial decree mandated by the Federal Government and invoked
by the private citizen. "It needs no argument to show that the political power cannot
be thus ousted of its jurisdiction and the judiciary set in its place." Louisiana
v. Jumel, 107 U. S. 711, 727-728 (1883).
By " `split[ting] the atom of sovereignty,' " the founders established " `two orders
of government, each with its own direct relationship, its own privity, its own set
of mutual rights and obligations to the people who sustain it and are governed by
it.' " Saenz v. Roe, 526 U. S. ____, ___, n. 17 (1999), quoting U. S. Term Limits,
Inc. v. Thornton, 514 U. S. 779, 838 (1995) (concurring opinion). "The Constitution
thus contemplates that a State's government will represent and remain accountable
to its own citizens." Printz, 521 U. S., at 920 . When the Federal Government asserts
authority over a State's most fundamental political processes, it strikes at the heart
of the political accountability so essential to our liberty and republican form of
government.
The asserted authority would blur not only the distinct responsibilities of the State
and National Governments but also the separate duties of the judicial and political
branches of the state governments, displacing "state decisions that `go to the heart
of representative government.' " Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U. S. 452, 461 (1991). A
State is entitled to order the processes of its own governance, assigning to the political
branches, rather than the courts, the responsibility for directing the payment of
debts. See id., at 460 ("Through the structure of its government, and the character
of those who exercise government authority, a State defines itself as a sovereign").
If Congress could displace a State's allocation of governmental power and responsibility,
the judicial branch of the State, whose legitimacy derives from fidelity to the law,
would be compelled to assume a role not only foreign to its experience but beyond
its competence as defined by the very constitution from which its existence derives.
Congress cannot abrogate the States' sovereign immunity in federal court; were the
rule to be different here, the National Government would wield greater power in the
state courts than in its own judicial instrumentalities. Cf. Howlett, 496 U. S., at
365 (noting the anomaly that would arise if "a State might be forced to entertain
in its own courts suits from which it was immune in federal court"); Hilton, 502 U.
S., at 206 (recognizing the "federalism-related concerns that arise when the National
Government uses the state courts as the exclusive forum to permit recovery under a
congressional statute").
The resulting anomaly cannot be explained by reference to the special role of the
state courts in the constitutional design. Although Congress may not require the legislative
or executive branches of the States to enact or administer federal regulatory programs,
see Printz, supra, at 935; New York, 505 U. S., at 188 , it may require state courts
of "adequate and appropriate" jurisdiction, Testa, 330 U. S., at 394 , "to enforce
federal prescriptions, insofar as those prescriptions relat[e] to matters appropriate
for the judicial power," Printz, supra, at 907. It would be an unprecedented step,
however, to infer from the fact that Congress may declare federal law binding and
enforceable in state courts the further principle that Congress' authority to pursue
federal objectives through the state judiciaries exceeds not only its power to press
other branches of the State into its service but even its control over the federal
courts themselves. The conclusion would imply that Congress may in some cases act
only through instrumentalities of the States. Yet, as Chief Justice Marshall explained,
"No trace is to be found in the constitution of an intention to create a dependence
of the government of the Union on those of the States, for the execution of the great
powers assigned to it. Its means are adequate to its ends; and on those means alone
was it expected to rely for the accomplishment of its ends." McCulloch v. Maryland,
4 Wheat. 316, 424 (1819); cf. Osborn v. Bank of United States, 9 Wheat. 738, 821 (1824)
("It is not insinuated, that the judicial power, in cases depending on the character
of the cause, cannot be exercised in the first instance, in the Courts of the Union,
but must first be exercised in the tribunals of the State").
The provisions of the Constitution upon which we have relied in finding the state
courts peculiarly amenable to federal command, moreover, do not distinguish those
courts from the Federal Judiciary. The Supremacy Clause does impose specific obligations
on state judges. There can be no serious contention, however, that the Supremacy Clause
imposes greater obligations on state-court judges than on the Judiciary of the United
States itself. The text of Article III, §1, which extends federal judicial power to
enumerated classes of suits but grants Congress discretion whether to establish inferior
federal courts, does give strong support to the inference that state courts may be
opened to suits falling within the federal judicial power. The Article in no way suggests,
however, that state courts may be required to assume jurisdiction that could not be
vested in the federal courts and forms no part of the judicial power of the United
States.
We have recognized that Congress may require state courts to hear only "matters appropriate
for the judicial power," Printz, 521 U. S., at 907 . Our sovereign immunity precedents
establish that suits against nonconsenting States are not "properly susceptible of
litigation in courts," Hans, 134 U. S., at 12 , and, as a result, that "[t]he `entire
judicial power granted by the Constitution' does not embrace authority to entertain
such suits in the absence of the State's consent." Principality of Monaco, 292 U.
S., at 329 (quoting Ex parte New York, 256 U. S., at 497 ); accord, 292 U. S., at
322 -323 (private suits against nonconsenting sovereigns are not "of a justiciable
character"). We are aware of no constitutional precept that would admit of a congressional
power to require state courts to entertain federal suits which are not within the
judicial power of the United States and could not be heard in federal courts. As we
explained in Erie R. Co. v. Tompkins, 304 U. S. 64 (1938):
"[T]he Constitution of the United States ... recognizes and preserves the autonomy
and independence of the States--independence in their legislative and independence
in their judicial departments. Supervision over either the legislative or the judicial
action of the States is in no case permissible except as to matters by the Constitution
specifically authorized or delegated to the United States. Any interference with either,
except as thus permitted, is an invasion of the authority of the State and, to that
extent, a denial of its independence." Id., at 78-79.
In light of history, practice, precedent, and the structure of the Constitution,
we hold that the States retain immunity from private suit in their own courts, an
immunity beyond the congressional power to abrogate by Article I legislation.
III
The constitutional privilege of a State to assert its sovereign immunity in its own
courts does not confer upon the State a concomitant right to disregard the Constitution
or valid federal law. The States and their officers are bound by obligations imposed
by the Constitution and by federal statutes that comport with the constitutional design.
We are unwilling to assume the States will refuse to honor the Constitution or obey
the binding laws of the United States. The good faith of the States thus provides
an important assurance that "[t]his Constitution, and the Laws of the United States
which shall be made in Pursuance thereof ... shall be the supreme Law of the Land."
U. S. Const., Art. VI.
Sovereign immunity, moreover, does not bar all judicial review of state compliance
with the Constitution and valid federal law. Rather, certain limits are implicit in
the constitutional principle of state sovereign immunity.
The first of these limits is that sovereign immunity bars suits only in the absence
of consent. Many States, on their own initiative, have enacted statutes consenting
to a wide variety of suits. The rigors of sovereign immunity are thus "mitigated by
a sense of justice which has continually expanded by consent the suability of the
sovereign." Great Northern Life Ins. Co. v. Read, 322 U. S., at 53 . Nor, subject
to constitutional limitations, does the Federal Government lack the authority or means
to seek the States' voluntary consent to private suits. Cf. South Dakota v. Dole,
483 U. S. 203 (1987).
The States have consented, moreover, to some suits pursuant to the plan of the Convention
or to subsequent constitutional amendments. In ratifying the Constitution, the States
consented to suits brought by other States or by the Federal Government. Principality
of Monaco, supra, at 328-329 (collecting cases). A suit which is commenced and prosecuted
against a State in the name of the United States by those who are entrusted with the
constitutional duty to "take Care that the Laws be faithfully executed," U. S. Const.,
Art. II, §3, differs in kind from the suit of an individual: While the Constitution
contemplates suits among the members of the federal system as an alternative to extralegal
measures, the fear of private suits against nonconsenting States was the central reason
given by the founders who chose to preserve the States' sovereign immunity. Suits
brought by the United States itself require the exercise of political responsibility
for each suit prosecuted against a State, a control which is absent from a broad delegation
to private persons to sue nonconsenting States.
We have held also that in adopting the Fourteenth Amendment, the people required
the States to surrender a portion of the sovereignty that had been preserved to them
by the original Constitution, so that Congress may authorize private suits against
nonconsenting States pursuant to its §5 enforcement power. Fitzpatrick v. Bitzer,
427 U. S. 445 (1976). By imposing explicit limits on the powers of the States and
granting Congress the power to enforce them, the Amendment "fundamentally altered
the balance of state and federal power struck by the Constitution." Seminole Tribe,
517 U. S., at 59 . When Congress enacts appropriate legislation to enforce this Amendment,
see City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U. S. 507 (1997), federal interests are paramount,
and Congress may assert an authority over the States which would be otherwise unauthorized
by the Constitution. Fitzpatrick, supra, at 456.
The second important limit to the principle of sovereign immunity is that it bars
suits against States but not lesser entities. The immunity does not extend to suits
prosecuted against a municipal corporation or other governmental entity which is not
an arm of the State. See, e.g., Mt. Healthy City Bd. of Ed. v. Doyle, 429 U. S., at
280 ; Lincoln County v. Luning, 133 U. S. 529 (1890). Nor does sovereign immunity
bar all suits against state officers. Some suits against state officers are barred
by the rule that sovereign immunity is not limited to suits which name the State as
a party if the suits are, in fact, against the State. See, e.g., In re Ayers, 123
U. S., at 505 -506; Idaho v. Coeur d'Alene Tribe of Idaho, 521 U. S., at 270 ("The
real interests served by the Eleventh Amendment are not to be sacrificed to elementary
mechanics of captions and pleading"). The rule, however, does not bar certain actions
against state officers for injunctive or declaratory relief. Compare Ex parte Young,
209 U. S. 123 (1908), and In re Ayers, supra , with Coeur d'Alene Tribe of Idaho,
supra, Seminole Tribe, supra, and Edelman v. Jordan, 415 U. S. 651 (1974). Even a
suit for money damages may be prosecuted against a state officer in his individual
capacity for unconstitutional or wrongful conduct fairly attributable to the officer
himself, so long as the relief is sought not from the state treasury but from the
officer personally. Scheuer v. Rhodes, 416 U. S. 232, 237-238 (1974); Ford Motor Co.
v. Department of Treasury of Ind., 323 U. S. 459, 462 (1945).
The principle of sovereign immunity as reflected in our jurisprudence strikes the
proper balance between the supremacy of federal law and the separate sovereignty of
the States. See Pennhurst State School and Hospital v. Halderman, 465 U. S., at 105
. Established rules provide ample means to correct ongoing violations of law and to
vindicate the interests which animate the Supremacy Clause. See Green v. Mansour,
474 U. S., at 68 . That we have, during the first 210 years of our constitutional
history, found it unnecessary to decide the question presented here suggests a federal
power to subject nonconsenting States to private suits in their own courts is unnecessary
to uphold the Constitution and valid federal statutes as the supreme law.
IV
The sole remaining question is whether Maine has waived its immunity. The State of
Maine "regards the immunity from suit as `one of the highest attributes inherent in
the nature of sovereignty,' " Cushing v. Cohen , 420 A. 2d 919, 923 (Me. 1981) (quoting
Drake v. Smith, 390 A. 2d 541, 543 (Me. 1978)), and adheres to the general rule that
"a specific authority conferred by an enactment of the legislature is requisite if
the sovereign is to be taken as having shed the protective mantle of immunity," 420
A. 2d, at 923 . Petitioners have not attempted to establish a waiver of immunity under
this standard. Although petitioners contend the State has discriminated against federal
rights by claiming sovereign immunity from this FLSA suit, there is no evidence that
the State has manipulated its immunity in a systematic fashion to discriminate against
federal causes of action. To the extent Maine has chosen to consent to certain classes
of suits while maintaining its immunity from others, it has done no more than exercise
a privilege of sovereignty concomitant to its constitutional immunity from suit. The
State, we conclude, has not consented to suit.
V
This case at one level concerns the formal structure of federalism, but in a Constitution
as resilient as ours form mirrors substance. Congress has vast power but not all power.
When Congress legislates in matters affecting the States, it may not treat these sovereign
entities as mere prefectures or corporations. Congress must accord States the esteem
due to them as joint participants in a federal system, one beginning with the premise
of sovereignty in both the central Government and the separate States. Congress has
ample means to ensure compliance with valid federal laws, but it must respect the
sovereignty of the States.
In apparent attempt to disparage a conclusion with which it disagrees, the dissent
attributes our reasoning to natural law. We seek to discover, however, only what the
Framers and those who ratified the Constitution sought to accomplish when they created
a federal system. We appeal to no higher authority than the Charter which they wrote
and adopted. Theirs was the unique insight that freedom is enhanced by the creation
of two governments, not one. We need not attach a label to our dissenting colleagues'
insistence that the constitutional structure adopted by the founders must yield to
the politics of the moment. Although the Constitution begins with the principle that
sovereignty rests with the people, it does not follow that the National Government
becomes the ultimate, preferred mechanism for expressing the people's will. The States
exist as a refutation of that concept. In choosing to ordain and establish the Constitution,
the people insisted upon a federal structure for the very purpose of rejecting the
idea that the will of the people in all instances is expressed by the central power,
the one most remote from their control. The Framers of the Constitution did not share
our dissenting colleagues' belief that the Congress may circumvent the federal design
by regulating the States directly when it pleases to do so, including by a proxy in
which individual citizens are authorized to levy upon the state treasuries absent
the States' consent to jurisdiction.
The case before us depends upon these principles. The State of Maine has not questioned
Congress' power to prescribe substantive rules of federal law to which it must comply.
Despite an initial good-faith disagreement about the requirements of the FLSA, it
is conceded by all that the State has altered its conduct so that its compliance with
federal law cannot now be questioned. The Solicitor General of the United States has
appeared before this Court, however, and asserted that the federal interest in compensating
the States' employees for alleged past violations of federal law is so compelling
that the sovereign State of Maine must be stripped of its immunity and subjected to
suit in its own courts by its own employees. Yet, despite specific statutory authorization,
see 29 U. S. C. §216(c), the United States apparently found the same interests insufficient
to justify sending even a single attorney to Maine to prosecute this litigation. The
difference between a suit by the United States on behalf of the employees and a suit
by the employees implicates a rule that the National Government must itself deem the
case of sufficient importance to take action against the State; and history, precedent,
and the structure of the Constitution make clear that, under the plan of the Convention,
the States have consented to suits of the first kind but not of the second. The judgment
of the Supreme Judicial Court of Maine is
Affirmed.
JOHN H. ALDEN, et al. , PETITIONERS v. MAINE
on writ of certiorari to the supreme judicial court of maine
[June 23, 1999]
Justice Souter , with whom Justice Stevens, Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer
join, dissenting.
In Seminole Tribe of Fla. v. Florida, 517 U. S. 44 (1996), a majority of this Court
invoked the Eleventh Amendment to declare that the federal judicial power under Article
III of the Constitution does not reach a private action against a State, even on a
federal question. In the Court's conception, however, the Eleventh Amendment was understood
as having been enhanced by a "background principle" of state sovereign immunity (understood
as immunity to suit), see id. , at 72, that operated beyond its limited codification
in the Amendment, dealing solely with federal citizen-state diversity jurisdiction.
To the Seminole Tribe dissenters, of whom I was one, the Court's enhancement of the
Amendment was at odds with constitutional history and at war with the conception of
divided sovereignty that is the essence of American federalism.
Today's issue arises naturally in the aftermath of the decision in Seminole Tribe
. The Court holds that the Constitution bars an individual suit against a State to
enforce a federal statutory right under the Fair Labor Standards Act of 1938 (FLSA),
29 U. S. C. §201 et seq. (1994 ed. and Supp. III) , when brought in the State's courts
over its objection. In thus complementing its earlier decision, the Court of course
confronts the fact that the state forum renders the Eleventh Amendment beside the
point, and it has responded by discerning a simpler and more straightforward theory
of state sovereign immunity than it found in Seminole Tribe: a State's sovereign immunity
from all individual suits is a "fundamental aspect" of state sovereignty "confirm[ed]"
by the Tenth Amendment. Ante , at 2, 3. As a consequence, Seminole Tribe 's contorted
reliance on the Eleventh Amendment and its background was presumably unnecessary;
the Tenth would have done the work with an economy that the majority in Seminole Tribe
would have welcomed. Indeed, if the Court's current reasoning is correct, the Eleventh
Amendment itself was unnecessary. Whatever Article III may originally have said about
the federal judicial power, the embarrassment to the State of Georgia occasioned by
attempts in federal court to enforce the State's war debt could easily have been avoided
if only the Court that decided Chisholm v. Georgia, 2 Dall. 419 (1793), had understood
a State's inherent, Tenth Amendment right to be free of any judicial power, whether
the court be state or federal, and whether the cause of action arise under state or
federal law.
The sequence of the Court's positions prompts a suspicion of error, and skepticism
is confirmed by scrutiny of the Court's efforts to justify its holding. There is no
evidence that the Tenth Amendment constitutionalized a concept of sovereign immunity
as inherent in the notion of statehood, and no evidence that any concept of inherent
sovereign immunity was understood historically to apply when the sovereign sued was
not the font of the law. Nor does the Court fare any better with its subsidiary lines
of reasoning, that the state-court action is barred by the scheme of American federalism,
a result supposedly confirmed by a history largely devoid of precursors to the action
considered here. The Court's federalism ignores the accepted authority of Congress
to bind States under the FLSA and to provide for enforcement of federal rights in
state court. The Court's history simply disparages the capacity of the Constitution
to order relationships in a Republic that has changed since the founding.
On each point the Court has raised it is mistaken, and I respectfully dissent from
its judgment.
I
The Court rests its decision principally on the claim that immunity from suit was
"a fundamental aspect of the sovereignty which the States enjoyed before the ratification
of the Constitution," ante , at 2, an aspect which the Court understands to have survived
the ratification of the Constitution in 1788 and to have been "confirm[ed]" and given
constitutional status, ante, at 3, by the adoption of the Tenth Amendment in 1791.
If the Court truly means by "sovereign immunity" what that term meant at common law,
see ante , at 25, its argument would be insupportable. While sovereign immunity entered
many new state legal systems as a part of the common law selectively received from
England, it was not understood to be indefeasible or to have been given any such status
by the new National Constitution, which did not mention it. See Seminole Tribe , supra
, at 132-142, 160-162, and n. 55 ( Souter , J., dissenting). Had the question been
posed, state sovereign immunity could not have been thought to shield a State from
suit under federal law on a subject committed to national jurisdiction by Article
I of the Constitution. Congress exercising its conceded Article I power may unquestionably
abrogate such immunity. I set out this position at length in my dissent in Seminole
Tribe and will not repeat it here. 1
The Court does not, however, offer today's holding as a mere corollary to its reasoning
in Seminole Tribe , substituting the Tenth Amendment for the Eleventh as the occasion
demands, and it is fair to read its references to a "fundamental aspect" of state
sovereignty as referring not to a prerogative inherited from the Crown, but to a conception
necessarily implied by statehood itself. The conception is thus not one of common
law so much as of natural law, a universally applicable proposition discoverable by
reason. This, I take it, is the sense in which the Court so emphatically relies on
Alexander Hamilton's reference in The Federalist No. 81 to the States' sovereign immunity
from suit as an "inherent" right, see ante , at 6, a characterization that does not
require, but is at least open to, a natural law reading.
I understand the Court to rely on the Hamiltonian formulation with the object of
suggesting that its conception of sovereign immunity as a "fundamental aspect" of
sovereignty was a substantially popular, if not the dominant, view in the periods
of Revolution and Confederation. There is, after all, nothing else in the Court's
opinion that would suggest a basis for saying that the ratification of the Tenth Amendment
gave this "fundamental aspect" its constitutional status and protection against any
legislative tampering by Congress. 2 The Court's principal rationale for today's result,
then, turns on history: was the natural law conception of sovereign immunity as inherent
in any notion of an independent State widely held in the United States in the period
preceding the ratification of 1788 (or the adoption of the Tenth Amendment in 1791)?
The answer is certainly no. There is almost no evidence that the generation of the
Framers thought sovereign immunity was fundamental in the sense of being unalterable.
Whether one looks at the period before the framing, to the ratification controversies,
or to the early republican era, the evidence is the same. Some Framers thought sovereign
immunity was an obsolete royal prerogative inapplicable in a republic; some thought
sovereign immunity was a common-law power defeasible, like other common-law rights,
by statute; and perhaps a few thought, in keeping with a natural law view distinct
from the common-law conception, that immunity was inherent in a sovereign because
the body that made a law could not logically be bound by it. Natural law thinking
on the part of a doubtful few will not, however, support the Court's position.
A
The American Colonies did not enjoy sovereign immunity, that being a privilege understood
in English law to be reserved for the Crown alone; "antecedent to the Declaration
of Independence, none of the colonies were, or pretended to be, sovereign states,"
1 J. Story, Commentaries on the Constitution §207, p. 149 (5th ed. 1891). Several
colonial charters, including those of Massachusetts, Connecticut, Rhode Island, and
Georgia, expressly specified that the corporate body established thereunder could
sue and be sued. See 5 Sources and Documents of United States Constitutions 36 (W.
Swindler ed. 1975) (Massachusetts); 2 id ., at 131 (Connecticut); 8 id ., at 363 (Rhode
Island); 2 id ., at 434 (Georgia). Other charters were given to individuals, who were
necessarily subject to suit. See Gibbons, The Eleventh Amendment and State Sovereign
Immunity: A Reinterpretation, 83 Colum. L. Rev. 1889, 1897 (1983). If a colonial lawyer
had looked into Blackstone for the theory of sovereign immunity, as indeed many did,
he would have found nothing clearly suggesting that the Colonies as such enjoyed any
immunity from suit. "[T]he law ascribes to the king the attribute of sovereignty ,
or pre-eminence," said Blackstone, 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries *241 (hereinafter
Blackstone), and for him, the sources for this notion were Bracton 3 and Acts of Parliament
that declared the Crown imperial. Id ., at *241-*242. It was simply the King against
whom "no suit or action can be brought ... even in civil matters, because no court
can have jurisdiction over him." Id ., at *242. 4 If a person should have "a just
demand upon the king, he must petition him in his court of chancery, where his chancellor
will administer right as a matter of grace though not upon compulsion." Id., at *243.
It is worth pausing here to note that after Blackstone had explained sovereign immunity
at common law, he went on to say that the common-law tradition was compatible with
sovereign immunity as discussed by writers on "natural law":
"And this is entirely consonant to what is laid down by the writers on natural law.
`A subject,' says Puffendorf, `so long as he continues a subject, hath no way to oblige
his prince to give him his due, when he refuses it; though no wise prince will ever
refuse to stand to a lawful contract. And, if the prince gives the subject leave to
enter an action against him, upon such contract, in his own courts, the action itself
proceeds rather upon natural equity, than upon the municipal laws.' For the end of
such action is not to compel the prince to observe the contract, but to persuade him."
Ibid . (footnote omitted). 5
Next Blackstone quoted Locke's explanation for immunity, according to which the risks
of overreaching by " `a heady prince' " are " `well recompensed by the peace of the
public and security of the government, in the person of the chief magistrate, being
thus set out of the reach of danger.' " Ibid . (quoting J. Locke, Second Treatise
of Civil Government §205 (1690 J. Gough ed. 1947)). By quoting Pufendorf and Locke,
Blackstone revealed to his readers a legal-philosophical tradition that derived sovereign
immunity not from the immemorial practice of England but from general theoretical
principles. But although Blackstone thus juxtaposed the common-law and natural law
6 conceptions of sovereign immunity, he did not confuse them. It was as well he did
not, for although the two conceptions were arguably "consonant" in England, where
according to Blackstone, the Crown was sovereign, 7 their distinct foundations could
make a difference in America, where the location of sovereignty was an issue that
independence would raise with some exigence.
B
Starting in the mid-1760's, ideas about sovereignty in colonial America began to
shift as Americans argued that, lacking a voice in Parliament, they had not in any
express way consented to being taxed. See B. Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the
American Revolution 204-219 (1968); G. Wood, The Creation of the American Republic,
1776-1787, pp. 347-348 (1969). The story of the subsequent development of conceptions
of sovereignty is complex and uneven; here, it is enough to say that by the time independence
was declared in 1776, the locus of sovereignty was still an open question, except
that almost by definition, advocates of independence denied that sovereignty with
respect to the American Colonies remained with the King in Parliament.
As the concept of sovereignty was unsettled, so was that of sovereign immunity. Some
States appear to have understood themselves to be without immunity from suit in their
own courts upon independence. 8 Connecticut and Rhode Island adopted their pre-existing
charters as constitutions, without altering the provisions specifying their suability.
See Gibbons, 83 Colum. L. Rev., at 1898, and nn. 42-43. Other new States understood
themselves to be inheritors of the Crown's common-law sovereign immunity and so enacted
statutes authorizing legal remedies against the State parallel to those available
in England. 9 There, although the Crown was immune from suit, the contemporary practice
allowed private litigants to seek legal remedies against the Crown through the petition
of right or the monstrans de droit in the Chancery or Exchequer. See 3 Blackstone
*256-257. A Virginia statute provided:
"Where the auditors according to their discretion and judgment shall disallow or
abate any article of demand against the commonwealth, and any person shall think himself
aggrieved thereby, he shall be at liberty to petition the high court of chancery or
the general court, according to the nature of his case, for redress, and such court
shall proceed to do right thereon; and a like petition shall be allowed in all other
cases to any other person who is entitled to demand against the commonwealth any right
in law or equity." 9 W. Hening, Statutes at Large: Being a Collection of the Laws
of Virginia 536, 540 (1821); see Pfander, Sovereign Immunity and the Right to Petition:
Toward a First Amendment Right to Pursue Judicial Claims Against the Government, 91
Nw. U. L. Rev. 899, 939-940, and n. 142 (1997).
This "petition" was clearly reminiscent of the English petition of right, as was
the language "shall proceed to do right thereon," which paralleled the formula of
royal approval, " soit droit fait al partie ," technically required before a petition
of right could be adjudicated. See 3 Blackstone *256; Pfander, supra , at 940, and
nn. 143-144. A New York statute similarly authorized petition to the court of chancery
by anyone who thought himself aggrieved by the state auditor general's resolution
of his account with the State. See An Act Directing a Mode for the Recovery of Debts
due to, and the Settlement of Accounts with this State, March 30, 1781, in The First
Laws of the State of New York 192 (1782 ed., reprinted 1984); see also Pfander, supra
, at 941, and n. 145.
Pennsylvania not only adopted a law conferring the authority to settle accounts upon
the Comptroller General, see Act of Apr. 13, 1782, ch. 959, 2 Laws of the Commonwealth
of Pennsylvania 19 (1810), but in 1785 provided for appeal from such adjudications
to the Pennsylvania Supreme Court, where a jury trial could be had, see id ., at 26-27;
Pfander, supra , at 941, n. 147. Although in at least one recorded case before the
Pennsylvania Supreme Court the Commonwealth, citing Blackstone, pleaded common-law
sovereign immunity, see Respublica v. Sparhawk , 1 Dall. 357, 363 (Pa. 1788), the
Supreme Court of Pennsylvania did not reach this argument, concluding on other grounds
that it lacked jurisdiction. 10 Two years after this decision, under the influence
of James Wilson, see C. Jacobs, The Eleventh Amendment and Sovereign Immunity 25,
and 169, n. 53 (1972), Pennsylvania adopted a new constitution, which provided that
"[s]uits may be brought against the commonwealth in such manner, in such courts, and
in such cases as the legislature may by law direct." Pa. Const., Art. IX, §11 (1790),
reprinted in 8 Sources and Documents of United States Constitutions, at 293; see also
Pfander, supra , at 928, n. 101. 11
Around the time of the Constitutional Convention, then, there existed among the States
some diversity of practice with respect to sovereign immunity; but despite a tendency
among the state constitutions to announce and declare certain inalienable and natural
rights of men and even of the collective people of a State, see, e.g., Pennsylvania
Constitution, Art. III (1776), 8 Sources and Documents of United States Constitutions,
supra , at 278 ("That the people of this State have the sole, exclusive and inherent
right of governing and regulating the internal police of the same"), no State declared
that sovereign immunity was one of those rights. To the extent that States were thought
to possess immunity, it was perceived as a prerogative of the sovereign under common
law. And where sovereign immunity was recognized as barring suit, provisions for recovery
from the State were in order, just as they had been at common law in England.
C
At the Constitutional Convention, the notion of sovereign immunity, whether as natural
law or as common law, was not an immediate subject of debate, and the sovereignty
of a State in its own courts seems not to have been mentioned. This comes as no surprise,
for although the Constitution required state courts to apply federal law, the Framers
did not consider the possibility that federal law might bind States, say, in their
relations with their employees. 12 In the subsequent ratification debates, however,
the issue of jurisdiction over a State did emerge in the question whether States might
be sued on their debts in federal court, and on this point, too, a variety of views
emerged and the diversity of sovereign immunity conceptions displayed itself.
The only arguable support for the Court's absolutist view that I have found among
the leading participants in the debate surrounding ratification was the one already
mentioned, that of Alexander Hamilton in The Federalist No. 81, where he described
the sovereign immunity of the States in language suggesting principles associated
with natural law:
"It is inherent in the nature of sovereignty not to be amenable to the suit of an
individual without its consent . This is the general sense and the general practice
of mankind; and the exemption, as one of the attributes of sovereignty, is now enjoyed
by the government of every State in the Union. Unless therefore, there is a surrender
of this immunity in the plan of the convention, it will remain with the States, and
the danger intimated [that States might be sued on their debts in federal court] must
be merely ideal. ... The contracts between a nation and individuals are only binding
on the conscience of the sovereign, and have no pretensions to a compulsive force.
They confer no right of action independent of the sovereign will." The Federalist
No. 81, pp. 548-549 (J. Cooke ed. 1961).
Hamilton chose his words carefully, and he acknowledged the possibility that at the
Convention the States might have surrendered sovereign immunity in some circumstances,
but the thrust of his argument was that sovereign immunity was "inherent in the nature
of sovereignty." 13 An echo of Pufendorf may be heard in his reference to "the conscience
of the sovereign"; 14 and the universality of the phenomenon of sovereign immunity,
which Hamilton claimed ("the general sense and the general practice of mankind"),
is a peculiar feature of the natural law conception. The apparent novelty and uniqueness
of Hamilton's employment of natural law terminology to explain the sovereign immunity
of the States is worth remarking, because it stands in contrast to formulations indicating
no particular position on the natural-law-versus-common-law origin, to the more widespread
view that sovereign immunity derived from common law, and to the more radical stance
that the sovereignty of the people made sovereign immunity out of place in the United
States. Hamilton's view is also worth noticing because, in marked contrast to its
prominence in the Court's opinion today, as well as in Seminole Tribe , 517 U. S.,
at 54 , and in Hans v. Louisiana, 134 U. S. 1, 13 (1890), cf. Great Northern Life
Ins. Co. v. Read, 322 U. S. 47, 51 (1944), it found no favor in the early Supreme
Court, see infra , at 21-22.
In the Virginia ratifying convention, Madison was among those who debated sovereign
immunity in terms of the result it produced, not its theoretical underpinnings. He
maintained that "[i]t is not in the power of individuals to call any state into court,"
3 J. Elliot, The Debates in the Several State Conventions on the Adoption of the Federal
Constitution 533 (2d ed. 1836) (hereinafter Elliot's Debates), and thought that the
phrase "in which a State shall be a Party" in Article III, §2, must be interpreted
in light of that general principle, so that "[t]he only operation it can have, is
that, if a state should wish to bring a suit against a citizen, it must be brought
before the federal court." Ibid. 15 John Marshall argued along the same lines against
the possibility of federal jurisdiction over private suits against States, and he
invoked the immunity of a State in its own courts in support of his argument:
"I hope that no gentleman will think that a state will be called at the bar of the
federal court. Is there no such case at present? Are there not many cases in which
the legislature of Virginia is a party, and yet the state is not sued? It is not rational
to suppose that the sovereign power should be dragged before a court." Id ., at 555.
There was no unanimity among the Virginians either on state- or federal-court immunity,
however, for Edmund Randolph anticipated the position he would later espouse as plaintiff's
counsel in Chisholm v. Georgia, 2 Dall. 419 (1793). He contented himself with agnosticism
on the significance of what Hamilton had called "the general practice of mankind,"
and argued that notwithstanding any natural law view of the nonsuability of States,
the Constitution permitted suit against a State in federal court: "I think, whatever
the law of nations may say, that any doubt respecting the construction that a state
may be plaintiff, and not defendant, is taken away by the words where a state shall
be a party ." 3 Elliot's Debates 573. Randolph clearly believed that the Constitution
both could and in fact by its language did trump any inherent immunity enjoyed by
the States; his view on sovereign immunity in state court seems to have been that
the issue was uncertain ("whatever the law of nations may say").
At the farthest extreme from Hamilton, James Wilson made several comments in the
Pennsylvania Convention that suggested his hostility to any idea of state sovereign
immunity. First, he responded to the argument that "the sovereignty of the states
is destroyed" if they are sued by the United States, "because a suiter in a court
must acknowledge the jurisdiction of that court, and it is not the custom of sovereigns
to suffer their names to be made use of in this manner." 2 id., at 490. For Wilson,
"[t]he answer [was] plain and easy: the government of each state ought to be subordinate
to the government of the United States." Ibid . 16 Wilson was also pointed in commenting
on federal jurisdiction over cases between a State and citizens of another State:
"When this power is attended to, it will be found to be a necessary one. Impartiality
is the leading feature in this Constitution; it pervades the whole. When a citizen
has a controversy with another state, there ought to be a tribunal where both parties
may stand on a just and equal footing." Id ., at 491. Finally, Wilson laid out his
view that sovereignty was in fact not located in the States at all: "Upon what principle
is it contended that the sovereign power resides in the state governments? The honorable
gentleman has said truly, that there can be no subordinate sovereignty. Now, if there
cannot, my position is, that the sovereignty resides in the people; they have not
parted with it; they have only dispensed such portions of the power as were conceived
necessary for the public welfare." Id ., at 443. 17 While this statement did not specifically
address sovereign immunity, it expressed the major premise of what would later become
Justice Wilson's position in Chisholm: that because the people, and not the States,
are sovereign, sovereign immunity has no applicability to the States.
From a canvass of this spectrum of opinion expressed at the ratifying conventions,
one thing is certain. No one was espousing an indefeasible, natural law view of sovereign
immunity. The controversy over the enforceability of state debts subject to state
law produced emphatic support for sovereign immunity from eminences as great as Madison
and Marshall, but neither of them indicated adherence to any immunity conception outside
the common law.
D
At the close of the ratification debates, the issue of the sovereign immunity of
the States under Article III had not been definitively resolved, and in some instances
the indeterminacy led the ratification conventions to respond in ways that point to
the range of thinking about the doctrine. Several state ratifying conventions proposed
amendments and issued declarations that would have exempted States from subjection
to suit in federal court. 18 The New York Convention's statement of ratification included
a series of declarations framed as proposed amendments, among which was one stating
"That the judicial power of the United States, in cases in which a state may be a
party, does not extend to criminal prosecutions, or to authorize any suit by any person
against a state." 1 Elliot's Debates 329. 19 Whether that amendment was meant to alter
or to clarify Article III as ratified is uncertain, but regardless of its precise
intent, New York's response to the draft proposed by the Convention of 1787 shows
that there was no consensus at all on the question of state suability (let alone on
the underlying theory of immunity doctrine). There was, rather, an unclear state of
affairs which it seemed advisable to stabilize.
The Rhode Island Convention, when it finally ratified on June 16, 1790, called upon
its representatives to urge the passage of a list of amendments. This list incorporated
language, some of it identical to that proposed by New York, in the following form:
"It is declared by the Convention, that the judicial power of the United States,
in cases in which a state may be a party, does not extend to criminal prosecutions,
or to authorize any suit by any person against a state; but, to remove all doubts
or controversies respecting the same, that it be especially expressed, as a part of
the Constitution of the United States, that Congress shall not, directly or indirectly,
either by themselves or through the judiciary, interfere with any one of the states
... in liquidating and discharging the public securities of any one state." 1 id.,
at 336.
Even more clearly than New York's proposal, this amendment appears to have been intended
to clarify Article III as reflecting some theory of sovereign immunity, though without
indicating which one.
Unlike the Rhode Island proposal, which hinted at a clarification of Article III,
the Virginia and North Carolina ratifying conventions proposed amendments that by
their terms would have fundamentally altered the content of Article III. The Virginia
Convention's proposal for a new Article III omitted entirely the language conferring
federal jurisdiction over a controversy between a State and citizens of another State,
see 3 id., at 660-661, and the North Carolina Convention proposed an identical amendment,
see 4 id., at 246-247. These proposals for omission suggest that the conventions of
Virginia and North Carolina thought they had subjected themselves to citizen suits
under Article III as enacted, and that they wished not to have done so. 20 There is,
thus, no suggestion in their resolutions that Article III as drafted was fundamentally
at odds with an indefeasible natural law sovereignty, or with a conception that went
to the essence of what it meant to be a State. At all events, the state ratifying
conventions' felt need for clarification on the question of state suability demonstrates
that uncertainty surrounded the matter even at the moment of ratification. This uncertainty
set the stage for the divergent views expressed in Chisholm .
E
If the natural law conception of sovereign immunity as an inherent characteristic
of sovereignty enjoyed by the States had been broadly accepted at the time of the
founding, one would expect to find it reflected somewhere in the five opinions delivered
by the Court in Chisholm v. Georgia, 2 Dall. 419 (1793). Yet that view did not appear
in any of them. And since a bare two years before Chisholm , the Bill of Rights had
been added to the original Constitution, if the Tenth Amendment had been understood
to give federal constitutional status to state sovereign immunity so as to endue it
with the equivalent of the natural law conception, one would be certain to find such
a development mentioned somewhere in the Chisholm writings. In fact, however, not
one of the opinions espoused the natural law view, and not one of them so much as
mentioned the Tenth Amendment. Not even Justice Iredell, who alone among the Justices
thought that a State could not be sued in federal court, echoed Hamilton or hinted
at a constitutionally immutable immunity doctrine.
Chisholm presented the questions whether a State might be made a defendant in a suit
brought by a citizen of another State, and if so, whether an action of assumpsit would
lie against it. See id ., at 420 (questions presented). 21 In representing Chisholm,
Edmund Randolph, the Framer 22 and then Attorney General, not only argued for the
necessity of a federal forum to vindicate private rights against the States, see id
., at 422, but rejected any traditional conception of sovereignty. He said that the
sovereignty of the States, which he acknowledged, id ., at 423, was no barrier to
jurisdiction, because "the present Constitution produced a new order of things. It
derives its origin immediately from the people ... . The States are in fact assemblages
of these individuals who are liable to process," ibid .
Justice Wilson took up the argument for the sovereignty of the people more vociferously.
Building on a conception of sovereignty he had already expressed at the Pennsylvania
ratifying convention, see supra , at 18-19, he began by noting what he took to be
the pregnant silence of the Constitution regarding sovereignty:
"To the Constitution of the United States the term SOVEREIGN, is totally unknown.
There is but one place where it could have been used with propriety. But, even in
that place it would not, perhaps, have comported with the delicacy of those, who ordained
and established the Constitution. They might have announced themselves `SOVEREIGN'
people of the United States: But serenely conscious of the fact , they avoided the
ostentatious declaration ." 2 Dall. at 454.
As if to contrast his own directness 23 with the Framers' delicacy, the Framer-turned-Justice
explained in no uncertain terms that Georgia was not sovereign with respect to federal
jurisdiction (even in a diversity case):
"As a Judge of this Court, I know, and can decide upon the knowledge, that the citizens
of Georgia , when they acted upon the large scale of the Union , as a part of the
`People of the United States,' did not surrender the Supreme or Sovereign Power to
that State; but, as to the purposes of the Union , retained it to themselves. As to
the purposes of the Union , therefore, Georgia is NOT a sovereign State ." Id ., at
457.
This was necessarily to reject any natural law conception of sovereign immunity as
inherently attached to an American State, but this was not all. Justice Wilson went
on to identify the origin of sovereign immunity in the feudal system that had, he
said, been brought to England and to the common law by the Norman Conquest. After
quoting Blackstone's formulation of the doctrine as it had developed in England, he
discussed it in the most disapproving terms imaginable:
"This last position [that the King is sovereign and no court can have jurisdiction
over him] is only a branch of a much more extensive principle, on which a plan of
systematic despotism has been lately formed in England , and prosecuted with unwearied
assiduity and care. Of this plan the author of the Commentaries was, if not the introducer,
at least the great supporter. He has been followed in it by writers later and less
known; and his doctrines have, both on the other and this side of the Atlantic, been
implicitly and generally received by those, who neither examined their principles
nor their consequences [.] The principle is, that all human law must be prescribed
by a superior . This principle I mean not now to examine. Suffice it, at present to
say, that another principle, very different in its nature and operations, forms, in
my judgment, the basis of sound and genuine jurisprudence; laws derived from the pure
source of equality and justice must be founded on the CONSENT of those, whose obedience
they require. The sovereign , when traced to his source, must be found in the man
." Id ., at 458.
With this rousing conclusion of revolutionary ideology and rhetoric, Justice Wilson
left no doubt that he thought the doctrine of sovereign immunity entirely anomalous
in the American Republic. Although he did not speak specifically of a State's immunity
in its own courts, his view necessarily requires that such immunity would not have
been justifiable as a tenet of absolutist natural law.
Chief Justice Jay took a less vehement tone in his opinion, but he, too, denied the
applicability of the doctrine of sovereign immunity to the States. He explained the
doctrine as an incident of European feudalism, id ., at 471, and said that by contrast,
"[n]o such ideas obtain here; at the Revolution, the sovereignty devolved on the
people; and they are truly the sovereigns of the country, but they are sovereigns
without subjects (unless the African slaves among us may be so called) and have none
to govern but themselves; the citizens of America are equal as fellow citizens, and
as joint tenants in the sovereignty." Id ., at 471-472.
From the difference between the sovereignty of princes and that of the people, Chief
Justice Jay argued, it followed that a State might be sued. When a State sued another
State, as all agreed it could do in federal court, all the people of one State sued
all the people of the other. "But why it should be more incompatible, that all the
people of a State should be sued by one citizen, than by one hundred thousand, I cannot
perceive, the process in both cases being alike; and the consequences of a judgment
alike." Id ., at 473. Finally, Chief Justice Jay pointed out, Article III authorized
suits between a State and citizens of another State. Although the Chief Justice reserved
judgment on whether the United States might be sued by a citizen, given that the courts
must rely on the Executive to implement their decisions, he made it clear that this
reservation was practical, and not theoretical: "I wish the State of society was so
far improved, and the science of Government advanced to such a degree of perfection,
as that the whole nation could in the peaceable course of law, be compelled to do
justice, and be sued by individual citizens." Id ., at 478. Although Chief Justice
Jay did not speak specifically to the question of state sovereign immunity in state
court, his theory shows that he considered not the States, but the people collectively,
to be sovereign; and there is thus no reason to think he would have denied that the
people of the Nation could override any state claim to sovereign immunity in a matter
committed to the Nation.
Justice Cushing's opinion relied on the express language of Article III to hold that
Georgia might be sued in federal court. He dealt shortly with the objection that States'
sovereignty would be thereby restricted so that States would be reduced to corporations:
"As to corporations, all States whatever are corporations or bodies politic. The only
question is, what are their powers?" Id ., at 468. Observing that the Constitution
limits the powers of the States in numerous ways, he concluded that "no argument of
force can be taken from the sovereignty of States. Where it has been abridged, it
was thought necessary for the greater indispensable good of the whole." Ibid . From
the opinion, it is not possible to tell with certainty what Justice Cushing thought
about state sovereign immunity in state court, although his introductory remark is
suggestive. The case, he wrote, "turns not upon the law or practice of England , although
perhaps it may be in some measure elucidated thereby, nor upon the law of any other
country whatever; but upon the Constitution established by the people of the United
States." Id ., at 466. It is clear that he had no sympathy for a view of sovereign
immunity inherent in statehood and untouchable by national legislative authority.
Justice Blair, like Justice Cushing, relied on Article III, and his brief opinion
shows that he acknowledged state sovereign immunity, but common-law immunity in state
court. First, Justice Blair asked hypothetically whether a verdict against the plaintiff
would be preclusive if the plaintiff "should renew his suit against the State, in
any mode in which she may permit herself to be sued in her own Courts." Id ., at 452.
Second, he commented that there was no need to require the plaintiff to proceed by
way of petition:
"When sovereigns are sued in their own Courts, such a method may have been established
as the most respectful form of demand; but we are not now in a State-Court; and if
sovereignty be an exemption from suit in any other than the sovereign's own Courts,
it follows that when a State, by adopting the Constitution, has agreed to be amenable
to the judicial power of the United States , she has, in that respect, given up her
right of sovereignty." Ibid .
It is worth noting that for Justice Blair, the petition brought in state court was
properly called a suit. This reflects the contemporary practice of his native Virginia,
where, as we have seen, supra , at 10-11, suits as of right against the State were
authorized by statute. Justice Blair called sovereignty "an exemption from suit in
any other than the sovereign's own Courts" because he assumed that, in its own courts,
a sovereign will naturally permit itself to be sued as of right.
Justice Iredell was the only Member of the Court to hold that the suit could not
lie; but if his discussion was far-reaching, his reasoning was cautious. Its core
was that the Court could not assume a waiver of the State's common-law sovereign immunity
where Congress had not expressly passed such a waiver. See 2 Dall., at 449 (dissenting
opinion). Although Justice Iredell added, in what he clearly identified as dictum,
that he was "strongly against" any construction of the Constitution "which will admit,
under any circumstances, a compulsive suit against a State for the recovery of money,"
ibid. , 24 he made it equally clear that he understood sovereign immunity
as a common-law doctrine passed to the States with
independence:
"No other part of the common law of England , it appears to me, can have any reference
to this subject, but that part of it which prescribes remedies against the crown.
Every State in the Union in every instance where its sovereignty has not been delegated
to the United States , I consider to be as compleatly sovereign, as the United States
are in respect to the powers surrendered. The United States are sovereign as to all
the powers of Government actually surrendered: Each State in the Union is sovereign
as to all the powers reserved. It must necessarily be so, because the United States
have no claim to any authority but such as the States have surrendered to them: Of
course the part not surrenderred must remain as it did before." Id ., at 435.
This did not mean, of course, that the States had not delegated to Congress the power
to subject them to suit, but merely that such a delegation would have been necessary
on Justice Iredell's view.
In sum, then, in Chisholm two Justices (Jay and Wilson), both of whom had been present
at the Constitutional Convention, took a position suggesting that States should not
enjoy sovereign immunity (however conceived) even in their own courts; one (Cushing)
was essentially silent on the issue of sovereign immunity in state court; one (Blair)
took a cautious position affirming the pragmatic view that sovereign immunity was
a continuing common law doctrine and that States would permit suit against themselves
as of right; and one (Iredell) expressly thought that state sovereign immunity at
common-law rightly belonged to the sovereign States. Not a single Justice suggested
that sovereign immunity was an inherent and indefeasible right of statehood, and neither
counsel for Georgia before the Circuit Court, see supra , at 24, n. 21, nor Justice
Iredell seems even to have conceived the possibility that the new Tenth Amendment
produced the equivalent of such a doctrine. This dearth of support makes it very implausible
for today's Court to argue that a substantial (let alone a dominant) body of thought
at the time of the framing understood sovereign immunity to be an inherent right of
statehood, adopted or confirmed by the Tenth Amendment. 25
The Court's discomfort is evident in its obvious recognition that its natural law
or Tenth Amendment conception of state sovereign immunity is insupportable if Chisholm
stands. Hence the Court's attempt to discount the Chisholm opinions, an enterprise
in which I believe it fails.
The Court, citing Hans v. Louisiana, 134 U. S. 1 (1890), says that the Eleventh Amendment
"overruled" Chisholm , ante , at 12, but the animadversion is beside the point. The
significance of Chisholm is its indication that in 1788 and 1791 it was not generally
assumed (indeed, hardly assumed at all) that a State's sovereign immunity from suit
in its own courts was an inherent, and not merely a comon-law, advantage. On the contrary,
the testimony of five eminent legal minds of the day confirmed that virtually everyone
who understood immunity to be legitimate saw it as a common-law prerogative (from
which it follows that it was subject to abrogation by Congress as to a matter within
Congress's Article I authority).
The Court does no better with its trio of arguments to undercut Chisholm 's legitimacy:
that the Chisholm majority "failed to address either the practice or the understanding
that prevailed in the States at the time the Constitution was adopted," ante , at
11; that "the majority suspected the decision would be unpopular and surprising,"
ibid . ; and that "two Members of the majority acknowledged that the United States
might well remain immune from suit despite" Article III, ante , at 12. These three
claims do not, of course, go to the question whether state sovereign immunity was
understood to be "fundamental" or "inherent," but in any case, none of them is convincing.
With respect to the first, Justice Blair in fact did expressly refer to the practice
of state sovereign immunity in state court, and acknowledged the petition of right
as an appropriate and normal practice. This aside, the Court would have a legitimate
point if it could show that the Chisholm majority took insufficient account of a body
of practice that somehow indicated a widely held absolutist conception of state sovereign
immunity untouchable and untouched by the Constitution. But of course it cannot. 26
As for the second point, it is a remarkable doctrine that would hold anticipation
of unpopularity the benchmark of constitutional error. In any event, the evidence
proffered by the Court is merely this: that Justice Wilson thought the prerevolutionary
conception of sovereignty misguided, 2 Dall., at 454-455; that Justice Cushing stated
axiomatically that the Constitution could always be amended, id ., at 468; that Chief
Justice Jay noted that the losing defendant might still come to understand that sovereign
immunity is inconsistent with republicanism, id ., at 478-479; and that Attorney General
Randolph admitted that the position he espoused was unpopular not only in Georgia,
but also in another State, probably Virginia. 27 These items boil down to the proposition
that the Justices knew (as who could not, with such a case before him) that at the
ratifying conventions the significance of sovereign immunity had been, as it still
was, a matter of dispute. This reality does not detract from, but confirms, the view
that the Framers showed no intent to recognize sovereign immunity as an immutably
inherent power of the States.
As to the third objection, that two Justices noted that the United States might possess
sovereign immunity notwithstanding Article III, I explained, supra , at 28, that Chief
Justice Jay thought this possibility was purely practical, not at all legal, and without
any implication for state immunity vis-à-vis federal claims. Justice Cushing was so
little troubled by the possibility he raised that he wrote, "If this be a necessary
consequence, it must be so," Chisholm , supra , at 469, and simply suggested a textual
reading that might have led to a different consequence.
Nor can the Court make good on its claim that the enactment of the Eleventh Amendment
retrospectively reestablished the view that had already been established at the time
of the framing (though eluding the perception of all but one Member of the Supreme
Court), and hence "acted ... to restore the original constitutional design," ante
, at 12. 28 There was nothing "established" about the position espoused by Georgia
in the effort to repudiate its debts, and the Court's implausible suggestion to the
contrary merely echoes the brio of its remark in Seminole Tribe that Chisholm was
"contrary to the well-understood meaning of the Constitution." 517 U. S., at 69 (citing
Principality of Monaco v. Mississippi, 292 U. S. 313, 325 (1934)). The fact that Chisholm
was no conceptual aberration is apparent from the ratification debates and the several
state requests to rewrite Article III. There was no received view either of the role
this sovereign immunity would play in the circumstances of the case or of a conceptual
foundation for immunity doctrine at odds with Chisholm 's reading of Article III.
As an author on whom the Court relies, see ante , at 14, has it, "there was no unanimity
among the Framers that immunity would exist," D. Currie, The Constitution in the Supreme
Court: The First Century 19 (1985). 29
It should not be surprising, then, to realize that although much post- Chisholm discussion
was disapproving (as the States saw their escape from debt cut off), the decision
had champions "every bit as vigorous in defending their interpretation of the Constitution
as were those partisans on the other side of the issue." Marcus & Wexler, Suits Against
States: Diversity of Opinion In The 1790s, 1993 J. Sup. Ct. Hist. 73, 83; see, e.g.,
5 Documentary History of the Supreme Court, supra , at 251-252, 252-253, 262-264,
268-269 (newspaper articles supporting holding in Chisholm ); 5 Documentary History,
supra n. 17, at 616 (statement of a Committee of Delaware Senate in support of holding
in Chisholm ). The federal citizen-state diversity jurisdiction was settled by the
Eleventh Amendment; Article III was not "restored."
F
It is clear enough that the Court has no historical predicate to argue for a fundamental
or inherent theory of sovereign immunity as limiting authority elsewhere conferred
by the Constitution or as imported into the Constitution by the Tenth Amendment. But
what if the facts were otherwise and a natural law conception of state sovereign immunity
in a State's own courts were implicit in the Constitution? On good authority, it would
avail the State nothing, and the Court would be no less mistaken than it is already
in sustaining the State's claim today.
The opinion of this Court that comes closer to embodying the present majority's inherent,
natural law theory of sovereign immunity than any other I can find was written by
Justice Holmes in Kawananakoa v. Polyblank, 205 U. S. 349 (1907). 30 I do not, of
course, suggest that Justice Holmes was a natural law jurist, see "Natural Law," in
O. Holmes, Collected Legal Papers 312 (1920) ("The jurists who believe in natural
law seem to me to be in that na ;ve state of mind that accepts what has been familiar
and accepted ... as something that must be accepted"). But in Kawananakoa he not only
gave a cogent restatement of the natural law view of sovereign immunity, but one that
includes a feature (omitted from Hamilton's formulation) explaining why even the most
absolutist version of sovereign immunity doctrine actually refutes the Court's position
today: the Court fails to realize that under the natural law theory, sovereign immunity
may be invoked only by the sovereign that is the source of the right upon which suit
is brought. Justice Holmes said so expressly: "A sovereign is exempt from suit, not
because of any formal conception or obsolete theory, but on the logical and practical
ground that there can be no legal right as against the authority that makes the law
on which the right depends." Kawananakoa , supra , at 353.
His cited authorities stand in the line that today's Court purports to follow: Hobbes,
Bodin, Sir John Eliot, and Baldus de Ubaldis. Hobbes, in the cited work, said this:
"The sovereign of a Commonwealth, be it an assembly or one man, is not subject to
the civil laws. For having power to make and repeal laws, he may, when he pleaseth,
free himself from that subjection by repealing those laws that trouble him, and making
of new; and consequently he was free before. For he is free that can be free when
he will: nor is it possible for any person to be bound to himself, because he that
can bind can release; and therefore he that is bound to himself only is not bound."
Leviathan ch. 26, §2, p. 130.
Jean Bodin produced a similar explanation nearly three-quarters of a century before
Hobbes, see J. Bodin, Les six livres de la republique, Bk. 1, ch. 8 (1577); Six Books
of the Commonwealth 28 (M. Tooley transl. 1967) ("[T]he sovereign ... cannot in any
way be subject to the commands of another, for it is he who makes law"). Eliot cited
Baldus for the crux of the theory: majesty is "a fulness of power subject to noe necessitie,
limitted within no rules of publicke Law," 1 J. Eliot, De Jure Maiestatis: or Political
Treatise of Government 15 (A. Grosart ed. 1882), and Baldus himself made the point
in observing that no one is bound by his own statute as of necessity, see Commentary
of Baldus on the statute Digna vox in Justinian's Code 1.14.4, Lectura super Codice
folio 51b (Chapter De Legibus et constitutionibus ) (Venice ed. 1496) (" nemo suo
statuto ligatur necessitative ").
The "jurists who believe in natural law" might have reproved Justice Holmes for his
general skepticism about the intrinsic value of their views, but they would not have
faulted him for seeing the consequence of their position: if the sovereign is not
the source of the law to be applied, sovereign immunity has no applicability. Justice
Holmes indeed explained that in the case of multiple sovereignties, the subordinate
sovereign will not be immune where the source of the right of action is the sovereign
that is dominant. See Kawananakoa , 205 U. S., at 353 , 354 (District of Columbia
not immune to private suit, because private rights there are "created and controlled
by Congress and not by a legislature of the District"). Since the law in this case
proceeds from the national source, whose laws authorized by Article I are binding
in state courts, sovereign immunity cannot be a defense. After Garcia v. San Antonio
Metropolitan Transit Authority, 469 U. S. 528 (1985), Justice Holmes's logically impeccable
theory yields the clear conclusion that even in a system of "fundamental" state sovereign
immunity, a State would be subject to suit eo nomine in its own courts on a federal
claim.
There is no escape from the trap of Holmes's logic save recourse to the argument
that the doctrine of sovereign immunity is not the rationally necessary or inherent
immunity of the civilians, but the historically contingent, and to a degree illogical,
immunity of the common law. But if the Court admits that the source of sovereign immunity
is the common law, it must also admit that the common-law doctrine could be changed
by Congress acting under the Commerce Clause. It is not for me to say which way the
Court should turn; but in either case it is clear that Alden's suit should go forward.
II
The Court's rationale for today's holding based on a conception of sovereign immunity
as somehow fundamental to sovereignty or inherent in statehood fails for the lack
of any substantial support for such a conception in the thinking of the founding era.
The Court cannot be counted out yet, however, for it has a second line of argument
looking not to a clause-based reception of the natural law conception or even to its
recognition as a "background principle," see Seminole Tribe , 517 U. S., at 72 , but
to a structural basis in the Constitution's creation of a federal system. Immunity,
the Court says, "inheres in the system of federalism established by the Constitution,"
ante , at 21, its "contours [being] determined by the founders' understanding, not
by the principles or limitations derived from natural law," ante , at 25. Again, "[w]e
look both to the essential principles of federalism and to the special role of the
state courts in the constitutional design." Ante , at 39. That is, the Court believes
that the federal constitutional structure itself necessitates recognition of some
degree of state autonomy broad enough to include sovereign immunity from suit in a
State's own courts, regardless of the federal source of the claim asserted against
the State. If one were to read the Court's federal structure rationale in isolation
from the preceding portions of the opinion, it would appear that the Court's position
on state sovereign immunity might have been rested entirely on federalism alone. If
it had been, however, I would still be in dissent, for the Court's argument that state
court sovereign immunity on federal questions is inherent in the very concept of federal
structure is demonstrably mistaken.
A
The National Constitution formally and finally repudiated the received political
wisdom that a system of multiple sovereignties constituted the "great solecism of
an imperium in imperio ," cf. Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution,
at 223. 31 Once "the atom of sovereignty" had been split, U. S. Term Limits, Inc.
v. Thornton, 514 U. S. 779, 838 (1995) ( Kennedy , J., concurring), the general scheme
of delegated sovereignty as between the two component governments of the federal system
was clear, and was succinctly stated by Chief Justice Marshall: "In America, the powers
of sovereignty are divided between the government of the Union, and those of the States.
They are each sovereign, with respect to the objects committed to it, and neither
sovereign with respect to the objects committed to the other." McCulloch v. Maryland,
4 Wheat. 316, 410 (1819). 32
Hence the flaw in the Court's appeal to federalism. The State of Maine is not sovereign
with respect to the national objective of the FLSA. 33 It is not the authority that
promulgated the FLSA, on which the right of action in this case depends. That authority
is the United States acting through the Congress, whose legislative power under Article
I of the Constitution to extend FLSA coverage to state employees has already been
decided, see Garcia v. San Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority, 469 U. S. 528 (1985),
and is not contested here.
Nor can it be argued that because the State of Maine creates its own court system,
it has authority to decide what sorts of claims may be entertained there, and thus
in effect to control the right of action in this case. Maine has created state courts
of general jurisdiction; once it has done so, the Supremacy Clause of the Constitution,
Art. VI, cl. 2, which requires state courts to enforce federal law and state-court
judges to be bound by it, requires the Maine courts to entertain this federal cause
of action. Maine has advanced no " `valid excuse,' " Howlett v. Rose, 496 U. S. 356,
369 (1990) (quoting Douglas v. New York, N. H. & H. R. Co., 279 U. S. 377, 387-88
(1929)), for its courts' refusal to hear federal-law claims in which Maine is a defendant,
and sovereign immunity cannot be that excuse, simply because the State is not sovereign
with respect to the subject of the claim against it. The Court's insistence that the
federal structure bars Congress from making States susceptible to suit in their own
courts is, then, plain mistake. 34
B
It is symptomatic of the weakness of the structural notion proffered by the Court
that it seeks to buttress the argument by relying on "the dignity and respect afforded
a State, which the immunity is designed to protect," ante , at 39 (quoting Idaho v.
Coeur d'Alene Tribe of Idaho, 521 U. S. 261, 268 (1997)), and by invoking the many
demands on a State's fisc, ante , at 41-42. Apparently beguiled by Gilded Era language
describing private suits against States as " `neither becoming nor convenient,' "
ante , at 39 (quoting In re Ayers, 123 U. S. 443, 505 (1887)), the Court calls "immunity
from private suits central to sovereign dignity," ante , at 4, and assumes that this
"dignity" is a quality easily translated from the person of the King to the participatory
abstraction of a republican State, see, e.g., ante , at 40 ("[C]ongressional power
to authorize private suits against nonconsenting States in their own courts would
be ... offensive to state sovereignty"). The thoroughly anomalous character of this
appeal to dignity is obvious from a reading of Blackstone's description of royal dignity,
which he sets out as a premise of his discussion of
sovereignty:
"First, then, of the royal dignity. Under every monarchical establishment, it is
necessary to distinguish the prince from his subjects... . The law therefore ascribes
to the king ... certain attributes of a great and transcendent nature; by which the
people are led to consider him in the light of a superior being, and to pay him that
awful respect, which may enable him with greater ease to carry on the business of
government. This is what I understand by the royal dignity, the several branches of
which we will now proceed to examine." 1 Blackstone *241.
It would be hard to imagine anything more inimical to the republican conception,
which rests on the understanding of its citizens precisely that the government is
not above them, but of them, its actions being governed by law just like their own.
Whatever justification there may be for an American government's immunity from private
suit, it is not dignity. 35 See United States v. Lee, 106 U. S. 196, 208 (1882).
It is equally puzzling to hear the Court say that "federal power to authorize private
suits for money damages would place unwarranted strain on the States' ability to govern
in accordance with the will of their citizens." Ante , at 41-42. So long as the citizens'
will, expressed through state legislation, does not violate valid federal law, the
strain will not be felt; and to the extent that state action does violate federal
law, the will of the citizens of the United States already trumps that of the citizens
of the State: the strain then is not only expected, but necessarily intended.
Least of all does the Court persuade by observing that "other important needs" than
that of the "judgment creditor" compete for public money, ante , at 42. The "judgment
creditor" in question is not a dunning bill- collector, but a citizen whose federal
rights have been violated, and a constitutional structure that stints on enforcing
federal rights out of an abundance of delicacy toward the States has substituted politesse
in place of respect for the rule of law. 36
III
If neither theory nor structure can supply the basis for the Court's conceptions
of sovereign immunity and federalism, then perhaps history might. The Court apparently
believes that because state courts have not historically entertained Commerce Clause-based
federal-law claims against the States, such an innovation carries a presumption of
unconstitutionality. See ante , at 34 (arguing that absence of statutes authorizing
suits against States in state court suggests an assumed absence of such power). At
the outset, it has to be noted that this approach assumes a more cohesive record than
history affords. In Hilton v. South Carolina Public Railways Comm'n, 502 U. S. 197
(1991) ( Kennedy , J.), a case the Court labors mightily to distinguish, see ante
, at 26-27, 37 we held that a state-owned railroad could be sued in state court under
the Federal Employers' Liability Act, 45 U. S. C. §§51-60, notwithstanding the lack
of an express congressional statement, because " `the Eleventh Amendment does not
apply in state courts.' " Hilton , supra , at 205 (quoting Will v. Michigan Dept.
of State Police, 491 U. S. 58, 63-64 (1989)). 38 But even if the record were less
unkempt, the problem with arguing from historical practice in this case is that past
practice, even if unbroken, provides no basis for demanding preservation when the
conditions on which the practice depended have changed in a constitutionally relevant
way.
It was at one time, though perhaps not from the framing, believed that "Congress'
authority to regulate the States under the Commerce Clause" was limited by "certain
underlying elements of political sovereignty ... deemed essential to the States' `separate
and independent existence.' " See Garcia , 469 U. S., at 547 -548 (quoting Lane County
v. Oregon, 7 Wall. 71, 76 (1869)). On this belief, the preordained balance between
state and federal sovereignty was understood to trump the terms of Article I and preclude
Congress from subjecting States to federal law on certain subjects. (From time to
time, wage and hour regulation has been counted among those subjects, see infra ,
at 52.) As a consequence it was rare, if not unknown, for state courts to confront
the situation in which federal law enacted under the Commerce Clause provided the
authority for a private right of action against a State in state court. The question
of state immunity from a Commerce Clause-based federal-law suit in state court thus
tended not to arise for the simple reason that acts of Congress authorizing such suits
did not exist.
Today, however, in light of Garcia , supra (overruling National League of Cities
v. Usery, 426 U. S. 833 (1976)), the law is settled that federal legislation enacted
under the Commerce Clause may bind the States without having to satisfy a test of
undue incursion into state sovereignty. "[T]he fundamental limitation that the constitutional
scheme imposes on the Commerce Clause to protect the `States as States' is one of
process rather than one of result." Garcia , supra , at 554. Because the commerce
power is no longer thought to be circumscribed, the dearth of prior private federal
claims entertained against the States in state courts does not tell us anything, and
reflects nothing but an earlier and less expansive application of the commerce power.
Least of all is it to the point for the Court to suggest that because the Framers
would be surprised to find States subjected to a federal-law suit in their own courts
under the commerce power, the suit must be prohibited by the Constitution. See ante
, at 31-34 (arguing on the basis of the "historical record" that the Constitution
would not have been adopted if it had been understood to allow suit against States
in state court under federal law). The Framers' intentions and expectations count
so far as they point to the meaning of the Constitution's text or the fair implications
of its structure, but they do not hover over the instrument to veto any application
of its principles to a world that the Framers could not have anticipated.
If the Framers would be surprised to see States subjected to suit in their own courts
under the commerce power, they would be astonished by the reach of Congress under
the Commerce Clause generally. The proliferation of Government, State and Federal,
would amaze the Framers, and the administrative state with its reams of regulations
would leave them rubbing their eyes. But the Framers' surprise at, say, the FLSA,
or the Federal Communications Commission, or the Federal Reserve Board is no threat
to the constitutionality of any one of them, for a very fundamental reason:
"[W]hen we are dealing with words that also are a constituent act, like the Constitution
of the United States, we must realize that they have called into life a being the
development of which could not have been foreseen completely by the most gifted of
its begetters. It was enough for them to realize or to hope that they had created
an organism; it has taken a century and has cost their successors much sweat and blood
to prove that they created a nation. The case before us must be considered in the
light of our whole experience and not merely in that of what was said a hundred years
ago." Missouri v. Holland, 252 U. S. 416, 433 (1920) (Holmes, J.).
" `We must never forget,' said Mr. Chief Justice Marshall in McCulloch , [4 Wheat.,
at] 407, `that it is a Constitution we are expounding.' Since then this Court has
repeatedly sustained the exercise of power by Congress, under various clauses of that
instrument, over objects of which the Fathers could not have dreamed." Olmstead v.
United States, 277 U. S. 438, 472 (1928) (Brandeis, J. dissenting).
IV
A
If today's decision occasions regret at its anomalous versions of history and federal
theory, it is the more regrettable in being the second time the Court has suddenly
changed the course of prior decision in order to limit the exercise of authority over
a subject now concededly within the Article I jurisdiction of the Congress. The FLSA,
which requires employers to pay a minimum wage, was first enacted in 1938, with an
exemption for States acting as employers. See Maryland v. Wirtz, 392 U. S. 183, 185-186
(1968). In 1966, it was amended to remove the state employer exemption so far as it
concerned workers in hospitals, institutions, and schools. See id ., at 186-187, and
n. 6. In Wirtz , the Court upheld the amendment over the dissent's argument that extending
the FLSA to these state employees was "such a serious invasion of state sovereignty
protected by the Tenth Amendment that it is ... not consistent with our constitutional
federalism." Id ., at 201 (opinion of Douglas, J.).
In 1974, Congress again amended the FLSA, this time "extend[ing] the minimum wage
and maximum hour provisions to almost all public employees employed by the States
and by their various political subdivisions." National League of Cities , 426 U. S.,
at 836 . This time the Court went the other way: in National League of Cities , the
Court held the extension of the Act to these employees an unconstitutional infringement
of state sovereignty, id ., at 852; for good measure, the Court overturned Wirtz ,
dismissing its reasoning as no longer authoritative, see 426 U. S., at 854 -855.
But National League of Cities was not the last word. In Garcia , decided some nine
years later, the Court addressed the question whether a municipally owned mass-transit
system was exempt from the FLSA. 469 U. S., at 534 , 536. In holding that it was not,
the Court overruled National League of Cities , see 469 U. S., at 557 , this time
taking the position that Congress was not barred by the Constitution from binding
the States as employers under the Commerce Clause, id ., at 554. As already mentioned,
the Court held that whatever protection the Constitution afforded to the States' sovereignty
lay in the constitutional structure, not in some substantive guarantee. Ibid . 39
Garcia remains good law, its reasoning has not been repudiated, and it has not been
challenged here.
The FLSA has not, however, fared as well in practice as it has in theory. The Court
in Seminole Tribe created a significant impediment to the statute's practical application
by rendering its damages provisions unenforceable against the States by private suit
in federal court. Today's decision blocking private actions in state courts makes
the barrier to individual enforcement a total one.
B
The Court might respond to the charge that in practice it has vitiated Garcia by
insisting, as counsel for Maine argued, Brief for Respondent 11-12, that the United
States may bring suit in federal court against a State for damages under the FLSA,
on the authority of United States v. Texas, 143 U. S. 621, 644-645 (1892). See also
Seminole Tribe , 517 U. S., at 71 , n. 14. It is true, of course, that the FLSA does
authorize the Secretary of Labor to file suit seeking damages, see 29 U. S. C. §216(c),
but unless Congress plans a significant expansion of the National Goverment's litigating
forces to provide a lawyer whenever private litigation is barred by today's decision
and Seminole Tribe , the allusion to enforcement of private rights by the National
Government is probably not much more than whimsy. Facing reality, Congress specifically
found, as long ago as 1974, "that the enforcement capability of the Secretary of Labor
is not alone sufficient to provide redress in all or even a substantial portion of
the situations where compliance is not forthcoming voluntarily." S. Rep. No. 93-690,
p. 27 (1974). One hopes that such voluntary compliance will prove more popular than
it has in Maine, for there is no reason today to suspect that enforcement by the Secretary
of Labor alone would likely prove adequate to assure compliance with this federal
law in the multifarious circumstances of some 4.7 million employees of the 50 States
of the Union. 40
The point is not that the difficulties of enforcement should drive the Court's decision,
but simply that where Congress has created a private right to damages, it is implausible
to claim that enforcement by a public authority without any incentive beyond its general
enforcement power will ever afford the private right a traditionally adequate remedy.
No one would think the remedy adequate if private tort claims against a State could
only be brought by the National Government: the tradition of private enforcement,
as old as the common law itself, is the benchmark. But wage claims have a lineage
of private enforcement just as ancient, and a claim under the FLSA is a claim for
wages due on work performed. Denying private enforcement of an FLSA claim is thus
on par with closing the courthouse door to state tort victims unaccompanied by a lawyer
from Washington.
So there is much irony in the Court's profession that it grounds its opinion on a
deeply rooted historical tradition of sovereign immunity, when the Court abandons
a principle nearly as inveterate, and much closer to the hearts of the Framers: that
where there is a right, there must be a remedy. Lord Chief Justice Holt could state
this as an unquestioned proposition already in 1702, as he did in Ashby v. White ,
6 Mod. 45, 53-54, 87 Eng. Rep. 808, 815 (K.B.):
"If an Act of Parliament be made for the benefit of any person, and he is hindered
by another of that benefit, by necessary consequence of law he shall have an action;
and the current of all the books is so." Ibid . (citation omitted). 41
Blackstone considered it "a general and indisputable rule, that where there is a
legal right, there is also a legal remedy, by suit or action at law, whenever that
right is invaded." 3 Blackstone *23. The generation of the Framers thought the principle
so crucial that several States put it into their constitutions. 42 And when Chief
Justice Marshall asked about Marbury, "If he has a right, and that right has been
violated, do the laws of his country afford him a remedy?," Marbury v. Madison, 1
Cranch 137, 162 (1803), the question was rhetorical, and the answer clear:
"The very essence of civil liberty certainly consists in the right of every individual
to claim the protection of the laws, whenever he receives an injury. One of the first
duties of government is to afford that protection. In Great Britain the king himself
is sued in the respectful form of a petition, and he never fails to comply with the
judgment of his court." Id ., at 163.
Yet today the Court has no qualms about saying frankly that the federal right to
damages afforded by Congress under the FLSA cannot create a concomitant private remedy.
The right was "made for the benefit of" petitioners; they have been "hindered by another
of that benefit"; but despite what has long been understood as the "necessary consequence
of law," they have no action, cf. Ashby , supra , at 55, 87 Eng. Rep., at 815. It
will not do for the Court to respond that a remedy was never available where the right
in question was against the sovereign. A State is not the sovereign when a federal
claim is pressed against it, and even the English sovereign opened itself to recovery
and, unlike Maine, provided the remedy to complement the right. To the Americans of
the founding generation it would have been clear (as it was to Chief Justice Marshall)
that if the King would do right, the democratically chosen Government of the United
States could do no less. 43 The Chief Justice's contemporaries might well have reacted
to the Court's decision today in the words spoken by Edmund Randolph when responding
to the objection to jurisdiction in Chisholm: "[The Framers] must have viewed human
rights in their essence, not in their mere form." 2 Dall., at 423.
V
The Court has swung back and forth with regrettable disruption on the enforceability
of the FLSA against the States, but if the present majority had a defensible position
one could at least accept its decision with an expectation of stability ahead. As
it is, any such expectation would be na ;ve. The resemblance of today's state sovereign
immunity to the Lochner era's industrial due process is striking. The Court began
this century by imputing immutable constitutional status to a conception of economic
self-reliance that was never true to industrial life and grew insistently fictional
with the years, and the Court has chosen to close the century by conferring like status
on a conception of state sovereign immunity that is true neither to history nor to
the structure of the Constitution. I expect the Court's late essay into immunity doctrine
will prove the equal of its earlier experiment in laissez-faire, the one being as
unrealistic as the other, as indefensible, and probably as fleeting.
FOOTNOTES
Footnote 1
The Court inexplicably protests that "the right to trial by jury and the prohibition
on unreasonable searches and seizures ... derive from the common law," ante , at 23,
but are nonetheless indefeasible. I cannot imagine how this could be thought relevant
to my argument. These rights are constitutional precisely because they are enacted
in the Sixth and Fourth Amendments, respectively, while the general prerogative of
sovereign immunity appears nowhere in the Constitution. My point is that the common-law
rights that were not enacted into the Constitution were universally thought defeasible
by statute.
Footnote 2
I am assuming that the Court does not put forward the theory of the "fundamental
aspect" as a newly derived conception of its own, necessarily comprehended by the
Tenth Amendment guarantee only as a result of logic independent of any intention of
the Framers. Nor does the Court argue, and I know of no reason to suppose, that every
legal advantage a State might have enjoyed at common law was assumed to be an inherent
attribute of all sovereignties, or was constitutionalized wholesale by the Tenth Amendment,
any more than the Ninth Amendment constitutionalized all common-law individual rights.
Footnote 3
Bracton is the earliest source for the common-law immunity of the King, and his explanation
is essentially practical: " Si autem ab eo petatur, cum breve non currat contra ipsum,
locus erit supplicationi, quod factum suum corrigat et emendet ." That is, "If [justice]
is asked of him, since no writ runs against him there will [only] be opportunity for
a petition, that he correct and amend his act." 2 Bracton, De Legibus et Consuetudinibus
Angliae 33 (G. Woodbine ed., S. Thorne transl. 1968) (London 1569 ed., folio 5b, Bk.
I, ch. 8). The fact that no writ ran against the King was "no peculiar privilege;
for no feudal lord could be sued in his own court." 3 W. Holdsworth, History of English
Law 465 (3d ed. 1927). " `He can not be compelled to answer in his own court, but
this is true of every petty lord of every petty manor; that there happens to be in
this world no court above his court is, we may say, an accident.' " See Nevada v.
Hall, 440 U. S. 410, 415 , n. 6 (1979) (quoting 1 F. Pollock & F. Maitland, History
of English Law 518 (2d ed. 1899)). It was this same view of the immunity that came
down to Blackstone, who cited Finch for the view that the King must be petitioned
and not sued. See H. Finch, Law, or a Discourse Thereof, in Four Books 255 (1678 ed.
reprinted 1992) ("Here in place of action against the King petition must be made unto
him in the Chancery, or in Parliament, for no action did ever lie against the K[ing]
at the Common Law, but the party is driven to his petition" (footnotes omitted));
1 Blackstone *242.
Footnote 4
As I explain, infra this page and 8-9, this common-law conception of sovereign immunity
differed from the natural-law version, which understood immunity as derived from the
fact that the sovereign was the font of the law, which could not bind him. I do not
dispute, indeed I insist, that in England it was the common-law version that existed,
and so it is beside the point for the Court to protest that the King could not be
sued under French law in his own courts, see ante , at 25; naturally not, since the
common-law conception was not couched in terms of who was the font of the law. This
said, I note that it is surprising for the Court to say that "[i]t is doubtful whether
the King was regarded ... as the font of the traditions and customs which formed the
substance of the common law," ibid. Although Bracton said that "law makes the king,"
2 Bracton, at 33, he also said that the unwritten law of England could properly be
called law only to the extent that "the authority of the king or prince [has] first
been added thereto," id ., at 19, and he spoke of "these English laws and customs,
by the authority of kings," id ., at 21. The judges who announced the common law sat
"in the place of the king," id ., at 20, and so in practice the common law certainly
derived from him. Thus, at least for the most part, "[t]he custom of the king's court
is the custom of England, and becomes the common law." 1 Pollock & Maitland, supra
n. 3, at 184. But for this, Blackstone would probably not have remarked that the natural
law theory produced a result "consonant" with the common law, 1 Blackstone *243; see
infra this page and 9.
Footnote 5
For the original of the quoted passage, see 1 S. Pufendorf, De Jure Naturae et Gentium
Libri Octo 915 (1688 ed. reprinted 1934); for a modern translation, see 2 S. Pufendorf,
De Jure Naturae et Gentium Libri Octo 1344-1345 (transl. C. & W. Oldfather 1934) (hereinafter
Pufendorf). Elsewhere in the same chapter, Pufendorf expressly derives the impossibility
of enforcing a King's promises against him from natural law theory: "Therefore, since
a king enjoys natural liberty, if he has discovered any fault in a pact of his making,
he can of his own authority serve notice upon the other party that he refuses to be
obligated by reason of that fault; nor does he have to secure of the other [party
to the pact] a release from a thing [namely, the pact] which, of its own nature, is
incapable of producing an obligation or right." Id ., at 1342-1343.
Footnote 6
The Court says that to call its approach "natural law" is "an apparent attempt to
disparage," ante , at 50. My object, however, is not to call names but to show that
the majority is wrong, and in doing that it is illuminating to explain the conceptual
tradition on which today's majority draws, one that can be traced to the Court's opinion
from its origins in Roman sources. I call this conception the "natural law" view of
sovereign immunity, despite the historical ambiguities associated with the term, because
the expression by such figures as Pufendorf, Hobbes, and Locke, of the doctrine that
the sovereign might not be sued, was associated with a concept of sovereignty itself
derived from natural law. See Pufendorf 1103-1104; T. Hobbes, Leviathan Part 2, chs.
17-18 (1651), in 23 Great Books of the Western World 99-104 (1952) (hereinafter Leviathan)
(describing sovereignty as the result of surrender of individual natural rights to
single authority); J. Locke, Second Treatise of Civil Government §§95-99 (1690 J.
Gough ed. 1947) (describing political community formed by individual consent out of
a state of nature). The doctrine that the sovereign could not be sued by his subjects
might have been thought by medieval civil lawyers to belong to jus gentium , the law
of nations, which was a type of natural law; or perhaps in its original form it might
have been understood as a precept of positive, written law. The earliest source for
this conception is a statement of Ulpian's recorded in the Digest, I.3.31, and much
interpreted by medieval jurists, " Princeps legibus solutus est "; "The emperor is
not bound by statutes." See 1 The Digest of Justinian 13 (T. Mommsen & P. Krueger
eds., A. Watson transl. 1985); Tierney, The Prince Is Not Bound by the Laws: Accursius
and the Origins of the Modern State, 5 Comparative Studies in Society and History
378 (1963); K. Pennington, The Prince and the Law, 1200-1600: Sovereignty and Rights
in the Western Legal Tradition 77-79 (1993). Through its reception and discussion
in the continental legal tradition, where it related initially to the Emperor, but
also eventually to a King, to the Pope, and even to a city-state, see id., at 90,
this conception of sovereign immunity developed into a theoretical model applicable
to any sovereign body. Thus Hobbes could begin his discussion of the subject by saying,
"The sovereign of a Commonwealth, be it an assembly or one man, is not subject to
the civil laws." Leviathan ch. 26, p. 130. There is debate on the degree to which
different medieval interpreters of the maxim Princeps legibus solutus est understood
natural or divine law to limit the prince's freedom from the statutes. See Tierney,
supra , at 390-394; Pennington, supra , at 206-208; J. Canning, The Political Thought
of Baldus de Ubaldis 74-79 (1987).
Footnote 7
A better formulation would have clarified that sovereignty resided in the King in
Parliament, which was the dominant view by the later 17th century. See, e.g., G. Wood,
The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787, p. 347 (1969).
Footnote 8
The Court claims that the doctrine of sovereign immunity was "universal in the States
when the Constitution was drafted and ratified," ante , at 5, but the examples of
Connecticut and Rhode Island suggest that this claim is overstated. It is of course
true that these States' preservation without comment of their colonial suability could
be construed merely as a waiver of sovereign immunity, and not as a denial of the
principle. But in light of these States' silence as to any change in their status
as suable bodies, it would be tendentious so to understand it. The Court relies for
its claim on Justice Iredell's statement in Chisholm v. Georgia, 2 Dall. 419 (1793),
that there was "no doubt" that no State had " `any particular Legislative mode, authorizing
a compulsory suit for the recovery of money against a State ... either when the Constitution
was adopted, or at the time the judicial act was passed.' " Ante , at 5 (quoting Chisholm,
supra, at 434-435). But as the cases of Rhode Island and Connecticut demonstrate,
Justice Iredell was simply wrong. As I have had occasion to say elsewhere, that an
assertion of historical fact has been made by a Justice of the Court does not make
it so. See Seminole Tribe of Fla. v. Florida, 517 U. S. 44, 107 , n. 5 (1996) (dissenting
opinion).
Footnote 9
The Court seems to think I have overlooked this point, that the exceptions imply
a rule, see ante , at 15 (provisions for chancery petitions "only confir[m]" immunity
enjoyed by these States). The reason for canvassing the spectrum of state thought
and practice is not to deny the undoubted place of sovereign immunity in most States'
courts, but to examine what turns out to be the scanty evidence that the States understood
sovereign immunity in the indefeasible, civilian, natural law sense, necessary to
support the Court's position here.
Footnote 10
In a suit against Virginia in the Court of Common Pleas for Philadelphia County,
Virginia pleaded sovereign immunity in natural law terms, and the sheriff was excused
from making return of the writ attaching Virginia's goods, see Nathan v. Virginia
, 1 Dall. 77, n. (1781), but this was only after the Supreme Executive Council of
the Commonwealth had already ordered the goods returned and, in any event, involved
the immunity of one State in the courts of another, and not the distinct immunity
of a State in her own courts, see Nevada v. Hall, 440 U. S., at 414 .
Footnote 11
Whether this formulation was a constitutional waiver of sovereign immunity or an
affirmative repudiation of its applicability is uncertain, but the broad language
opening the courts to all suits, and the apparent desire to exceed the previously
available statutory scheme, would appear to support the latter interpretation.
Footnote 12
The Court says, "the founders' silence is best explained by the simple fact that
no one, not even the Constitution's most ardent opponents, suggested the document
might strip States of the immunity." Ante , at 31-32. In fact, a stalwart supporter
of the Constitution, James Wilson, laid the groundwork for just such a view at the
Pennsylvania Convention, see infra , at 18-19. For the most part, it is true, the
surviving records of the ratifying conventions do not suggest that much thought was
given to the issue of suit against States in their own courts. But this silence does
not tell us that the Framers' generation thought the prerogative so well settled as
to be an inherent right of States, and not a common-law creation. It says only that
at the conventions, the issue was not on the participants' minds because the nature
of sovereignty was not always explicitly addressed.
Footnote 13
In Seminole Tribe , I explained that Hamilton had in mind state sovereign immunity
only with respect to diversity cases applying state contract law. See 517 U. S., at
145 -149 (dissenting opinion). Here I intend simply to point out that with respect
to state law, in the main Hamilton spoke consistently with deriving sovereign immunity
from a natural law model. That he did so is consistent with his focus on state law;
Hamilton almost certainly knew that the natural law theory of sovereign immunity extended
only to rights created by the sovereign, and so would not have applied to federal-question
claims against a State in either state or federal court. Thus when the Court claims
that subjecting States to suit in state court "would turn on its head the concern
of the founding generation--that Article III might be used to circumvent state-court
immunity" ante , at 34, it has failed to realize that even those Framers who, like
Hamilton, aimed to preserve state sovereign immunity, had in mind only state immunity
on state-law claims, not federal questions.
Footnote 14
Pufendorf's discussion of sovereign immunity, just before the passage quoted by Blackstone,
begins (in a modern translation): "Now although promises and pacts are as binding
upon the conscience of a king as upon that of any private citizen, there is, nevertheless,
this difference between the obligation of a king and that of subjects, namely, that
it is no trouble for the former to exact what is owed him from a subject, when he
demurs, while a citizen, so long as he remains such, has no means within his power
to recover his due from a king against his will." 2 Pufendorf 1344-1345.
Footnote 15
Madison seems here to have overlooked the possibility of concurrent jurisdiction
between the Supreme Court's original jurisdiction and that of state courts.
Footnote 16
The Court says this statement of Wilson's is "startling even today," ante , at 15,
but it is hard to see what is so startling, then or now, about the proposition that,
since federal law may bind state governments, the state governments are in this sense
subordinate to the national. The Court seems to have forgotten that one of the main
reasons a Constitutional Convention was necessary at all was that under the Articles
of Confederation Congress lacked the effective capacity to bind the States. The Court
speaks as if the Supremacy Clause did not exist, or McCulloch v. Maryland, 4 Wheat.
316 (1819), had never been decided.
Nor is the Court correct to say that the views of Wilson, Randolph, and General Charles
Cotesworth Pinckney, see n. 17, infra , "cannot bear the weight" I put upon them,
ante , at 15. Indeed, the yoke is light, since I intend these Framers only to do their
part in showing that a diversity of views with respect to sovereignty and sovereign
immunity existed at the several state conventions, and that this diversity stands
in the way of the Court's assumption that the founding generation understood sovereign
immunity in the natural law sense as indefeasibly "fundamental" to statehood.
Finally, the Court calls Wilson's view "a radical nationalist vision of the constitutional
design," ante , at 15, apparently in an attempt to discount it. But while Wilson's
view of sovereignty was indeed radical in its deviation from older conceptions, this
hardly distanced him from the American mainstream, and in October 1787, Washington
himself called Wilson "as able, candid, & honest a member as any in Convention," 5
Papers of George Washington: Confederation Series 379 (W. Abbot & D. Twohig eds. 1997).
Footnote 17
Nor was Wilson alone in this theory. At the South Carolina Convention, General Charles
Cotesworth Pinckney, who had attended the Philadelphia Convention, took the position
that the States never enjoyed individual and unfettered sovereignty, because the Declaration
of Independence was an act of the Union, not of the particular States. See 4 Elliot's
Debates 301. In his view, the Declaration "sufficiently confutes the ... doctrine
of the individual sovereignty and independence of the several states... . The separate
independence and individual sovereignty of the several states were never thought of
by the enlightened band of patriots who framed this Declaration; the several states
are not even mentioned by name in any part of it,--as if it was intended to impress
this maxim on America, that our freedom and independence arose from our union, and
that without it we could neither be free nor independent." Ibid .
Footnote 18
"[T]he grand objection, that the states were made subject to the action of an individual,
still remained for several years, notwithstanding the concurring dissent of several
states at the time of accepting the constitution." St. G. Tucker, 1 Blackstone's Commentaries
with Notes of Reference to the Constitution and Laws of the Federal Government of
the United States; and of the Commonwealth of Virginia, App. 352 (1803). In a footnote,
Tucker specified that "[t]he several conventions of Massachusetts, New Hampshire,
Rhode Island, New York, Virginia, and North Carolina, proposed amendments in this
respect." Ibid . The proposed amendments of the latter four States, which may be found
in Elliot's Debates, are discussed immediately infra , at 21-23. The extant published
versions of the proposed amendments of Massachusetts and New Hampshire do not include
such a proposed amendment. See, e.g., 1 Elliot's Debates, 322-323 (nine proposed amendments
of Massachusetts); 2 id., at 177-178 (same); H. R. Doc. No. 398, 69th Cong., 1st Sess.,
1018-1020 (1927) (same); 1 Elliot's Debates, 325-326 (12 proposed amendments of New
Hampshire); H. R. Doc. No. 398, supra , at 1025-1026 (same).
Footnote 19
It is conceivable that the New York Convention, which was after all the intended
audience for The Federalist, thought that the States had some sort of an inherent
right against being sued in federal court. But this is unlikely, because numerous
other of the proposed amendments declared so-called "rights" in no uncertain terms,
see, e.g ., 1 Elliot's Debates 328 ("[T]he people have an equal, natural, and unalienable
right freely and peaceably to exercise their religion"; trial by jury is "one of the
greatest securities to the rights of a free people"; "[T]he people have a right peaceably
to assemble together"), whereas the proposed amendment regarding suits against States
simply stated that the judicial power "does not extend ... to authorize any suit by
any person against a state," and said nothing about any rights, inherent or otherwise.
Id., at 329.
Footnote 20
The Court says "there is no evidence that [the proposed amendments] were directed
toward the question of sovereign immunity or that they reflect an understanding that
the States would be subject to private suits without consent under Article III as
drafted." Ante , at 15. No evidence, that is, except the proposed amendments themselves,
which would have omitted the Citizen-State Diversity Clause. If the proposed omission
is not evidence going to sovereign immunity to private suits, one wonders what would
satisfy the Court.
Footnote 21
The case had first been brought before the Federal Circuit Court for the District
of Georgia, over which Justice Iredell and District Judge Nathaniel Pendleton had
presided. Ultimately, Justice Iredell held that the Circuit Court had no jurisdiction
in the case because Congress had not conferred such jurisdiction on it. See 5 Documentary
History of the Supreme Court of the United States, 1789-1800, pp. 128-129, 154 (M.
Marcus ed. 1994). Georgia had maintained that it was "a free, sovreign, and independent
State, and ... cannot be drawn or compelled, nor at any Time past hath been accustomed
to be, or could be drawn or compelled to answer against the will of the said State
of Georgia, before any Justices of the federal Circuit Court for the District of Georgia
or before any Justices of any Court of Law or Equity whatever." Plea to the Jurisdiction,
Oct. 17, 1791, id ., at 143. Chisholm demurred to the plea on the apparent ground
that while the plea alleged that Georgia could not be compelled to appear before any
court, Article III expressly declared that the federal judicial power extended to
all controversies between a State and citizens of another State. Demurrer, id ., at
144. In his unreported opinion, Justice Iredell dispensed with this demurrer. He first
stated that the plea sufficiently alleged that the District Court lacked jurisdiction.
Id ., at 150. He added that in any case, the existence of Congress's constitutional
authority to create courts to hear controversies between a State and citizens of another
State did not mean that Congress had in fact created such courts. Id ., at 151. Third,
Justice Iredell pointed out that the right to create courts for cases in which a State
was a party did not mean that Congress could confer jurisdiction in cases like the
one at bar, because the word "controversies" in Article III might refer only to situations
"where such controversies could formerly have been maintained" in state court. Since
"under the jurisdiction of a particular State Sovereigns may be liable in some instances
but not in others," just as "[i]n England the property in possession of the crown
can be affected by an adverse Process, tho' certainly the King cannot be sued for
the recovery of a sum of money," ibid. , it appeared to Justice Iredell that under
some conditions Article III did not authorize suits against States.
Footnote 22
Framer but not signer.
Footnote 23
Justice Wilson hinted that in his own private view, citizens of the States had not
conferred sovereignty in the sense of absolute authority upon their state governments,
because they had retained some rights to themselves: "[A]ccording to some writers,
every State, which governs itself without any dependence on another power, is a sovereign
State. Whether, with regard to her own citizens, this is the case of the State of
Georgia; whether those citizens have done, as the individuals of England are said,
by their late instructors, to have done, surrendered the Supreme Power to the State
or Government, and reserved nothing to themselves; or whether, like the people of
other States, and of the United States , the citizens of Georgia have reserved the
Supreme Power in their own hands; and on that Supreme Power have made the State dependent
, instead of being sovereign; these are questions, to which, as a Judge in this cause,
I can neither know nor suggest the proper answers; though, as a citizen of the Union
, I know, and am interested to know, that the most satisfactory answers can be given."
Chisholm , 2 Dall. 457, at (1793) (citation omitted).
Footnote 24
The basis for the dictum may be found earlier in the opinion, where Justice Iredell
explained that it was uncertain whether Article III's extension of the federal judicial
power to cases between a State and citizens of another State "is to be construed as
intending merely a transfer of jurisdiction from one tribunal to another, or as authorizing
the Legislature to provide laws for the decision of all possible controversies in
which a State may be involved with an individual, without regard to any prior exemption."
Id ., at 436. Justice Iredell seems to have believed that Article III authorized only
the former; in other words, that the Framers intended to permit Article III jurisdiction
in suits against a State only where some other existing court could also hear such
a claim. Because in Justice Iredell's view, state courts could nowhere hear suits
against a State at the time of ratification, see id ., at 434-435, it followed that
Article III probably did not authorize such suits. Justice Iredell's reasoning, it
must be said, differed markedly from the reasoning the Court adopts today. Justice
Iredell believed simply that the Clause in Article III extending jurisdiction to controversies
between a State and citizens of another State did not confer any extra law-making
authority on Congress that was not found elsewhere in the Constitution. Because he
could conceive of no other constitutional provision authorizing Congress to create
a private right of action against a State, he concluded that none could exist. Today,
of course, it is established that the commerce power authorizes Congress to create
private rights as against the States. See Garcia v. San Antonio Metropolitan Transit
Authority, 469 U. S. 528 (1985). The Court today takes the altogether different tack
of arguing that state immunity from suit in state court was an inherent right of States
preserved by the Tenth Amendment. Whatever Justice Iredell might have thought of this
argument, it gets no support from his opinion.
Footnote 25
It only makes matters worse for the Court that two States, New York and Maryland,
voluntarily subjected themselves to suit in the Supreme Court around the time of Chisholm
. See Marcus & Wexler, Suits Against States: Diversity of Opinion In The 1790s, 1993
J. Sup. Ct. Hist. 73, 74-78. At the Court's February Term, 1791, before Chisholm ,
Maryland entered a plea (probably as to the merits) in Van Staphorst v. Maryland ,
see 1993 J. Sup. Ct. Hist., at 74, a suit brought by a foreign citizen for debts owed
by the State, but then settled the suit to avoid the establishment of an adverse precedent
on immunity, see id ., at 75. In Oswald v. New York , an action that commenced before
Chisholm but that was continued after it, New York initially objected to jurisdiction,
see 1993 J. Sup. Ct. Hist., at 77, but the suit was tried to a jury in the Supreme
Court, and after New York lost, it paid the full jury verdict out of the State's treasury,
id ., at 78.
Footnote 26
The Court thinks that Justice Iredell's adversion to state practice gives reason
to think so, see ante , at 11 ("[D]espite the opinion of Justice Iredell, the majority
failed to address ..."). Even if Justice Iredell had been right about state practice,
failure to respond to a specific argument raised by another Justice (as opposed to
counsel) has even less significance with respect to this early Supreme Court opinion
than it would have today, because the Justices may not have afforded one another the
opportunity to read their opinions before they were announced. See 1 J. Goebel, the
Oliver Wendell Holmes Devise: History of the Supreme Court of the United States, Antecedents
and Beginnings to 1801, p. 728 (1971) ("There are hints ... that there may have been
no conference and that each Justice arrived at his conclusion independently without
knowing what each of his brethren had decided"). Indeed, since "opinions were given
only orally in the Supreme Court in the 1790s," 5 Documentary History of the Supreme
Court, supra n. 21, at 164, n., it is possible that the opinion as reported by Dallas
followed a document prepared by Wilson after the oral announcement of the opinion,
ibid.; see also id ., at xxiv-xxv, in which case it is possible that the other Justices
never heard certain arguments until publication.
Footnote 27
The circumlocution "another State, whose will must be always dear to me," Chisholm
, 2 Dall., at 419, hints at Randolph's home State. It seems odd to suggest that Randolph's
acknowledgment of the unpopularity of his position in two States would somehow support
the thought that the view was incorrect. Randolph himself had urged the same position
at the Virginia ratifying convention, see supra , at 16-17, and so knew perfectly
well that Virginia had ratified with full knowledge that his position might be the
law.
Footnote 28
It is interesting to note a case argued in the Supreme Court of Pennsylvania in 1798,
in which counsel for the Commonwealth urged a version of the point that the Court
makes here, and said that "[t]he language of the amendment, indeed, does not import
an alteration of the Constitution, but an authoritative declaration of its true construction."
Respublica v. Cobbet , 3 Dall. 467, 472 (Pa. 1798). The Court expressly repudiated
the historical component of this claim in an opinion by its Chief Justice: "When the
judicial law [ i.e. , the Judiciary Act of 1789] was passed, the opinion prevailed
that States might be sued, which by this amendment is settled otherwise." Id ., at
475 (M'Kean, C. J.).
Footnote 29
The Court might perhaps respond that if the role of state sovereign immunity was
not the subject of universal consensus in 1792, the enactment of the Eleventh Amendment
brought the doctrine into the constitutional realm. The strongest form of this view
must maintain that, notwithstanding the Amendment's silence regarding state courts
and its exclusive focus on the federal judicial power, the motivation of the Framers
of the Eleventh Amendment must have been affirmatively to embrace the position that
the States enjoyed the immunity from suit previously enjoyed by the Crown. On this
account, the Framers of the Eleventh Amendment said nothing about sovereign immunity
in state court because it never occurred to them that such immunity could be questioned;
had they thought of this possibility, they would have considered it absurd that States
immune in federal court could be subjected to suit in their own courts.
The first trouble with this view is that it assumes that the Eleventh Amendment was
intended to reach all federal law suits, and not only those arising under diversity
jurisdiction. If the Framers of the Eleventh Amendment had in mind only diversity
cases, as the Court was prepared to concede in Seminole Tribe , see 517 U. S., at
69 -70 ("The text dealt in terms only with the problem presented by the decision in
Chisholm ... . [I]t seems unlikely that much thought was given to the prospect of
federal-question jurisdiction over the States"), then it might plausibly follow that
the Framers of that Amendment assumed that States possessed sovereign immunity in
their own courts with respect to state law. But it certainly does not follow that
the Amendment's authors would have thought that States enjoyed immunity in state court
on questions of federal law. To accept this would require one to believe that the
Framers of the Eleventh Amendment were blind to an extremely anomalous application
of sovereign immunity, under which a State is immune even when it is not the font
of the law under which it is sued, cf. infra , at 39, 41. The Court today may labor
under the misapprehension that sovereign immunity can apply where the sovereign is
not the font of law, but the Court adduces no evidence to suggest that the Framers
of the Eleventh Amendment held such a view. And the Framers were much closer than
the Court to the theory of sovereign immunity according to which the font of law may
not be subject to suit under that law. This leaves the Court in the position of supporting
its view of what the Eleventh Amendment means by the "historical" assertion that the
Framers must have intended it to mean the same.
Footnote 30
The temptation to look to the natural law conception had shown up occasionally before
Justice Holmes's appointment, and goes back at least to Beers v. Arkansas, 20 How.
527 (1858), in which Chief Justice Taney wrote for the Court that "[i]t is an established
principle of jurisprudence in all civilized nations that the sovereign cannot be sued
in its own courts, or in any other, without its consent and permission," id ., at
529. But nothing turned on this pronouncement, because the outcome in the case would
have been the same had sovereign immunity been understood as a common-law property
of the States. In Nichols v. United States, 7 Wall. 122 (1869), Justice Davis wrote
that "[e]very government has an inherent right to protect itself against suits ...
. The principle is fundamental, [and] applies to every sovereign power ... ." Id .,
at 126. This description came in dicta, and the origin of the immunity had no bearing
on the decision. Justice Bradley quoted both Hamilton and Chief Justice Taney in Hans
v. Louisiana, 134 U. S. 1, 13 , 17 (1890), but nothing there depended on the natural
law approach, and in the main the opinion, whatever its other demerits, see Seminole
Tribe , supra , at 119 ( Souter , J. dissenting), understood state sovereign immunity
as a common-law concept, see Hans , supra , at 16 ("The suability of a State without
its consent was a thing unknown to the law"). And the Court in Seminole Tribe may
possibly have intended to hint at the natural law background of sovereign immunity
when it said approvingly that the decision in Hans " `found its roots not solely in
the common law of England, but in the much more fundamental "jurisprudence in all
civilized nations." ' " Seminole Tribe , supra , at 69 (quoting Hans , supra , at
17, in turn quoting Beers v . Arkansas, supra, at 529). The Court's occasional seduction
by the natural law view should not, however, obscure its basic adherence to the common-law
approach. In United States v. Lee, 106 U. S. 196 (1882), the Court explained that
"the doctrine is derived from the laws and practices of our English ancestors," id
., at 205, and added approvingly that the petition of right "has been as efficient
in securing the rights of suitors against the crown in all cases appropriate to judicial
proceedings, as that which the law affords to the subjects of the King in legal controversies
among themselves," ibid . The Court went on to notice that at common law one reason
given for sovereign immunity was the "absurdity" of the King's writ running against
the King, id ., at 206, but, recognizing the distinct situation in the United States,
the Court admitted candidly that "it is difficult to see on what solid foundation
of principle the exemption from liability to suit rests," ibid . Even the dissent
there discussed in great detail the common-law heritage of the doctrine. See id .,
at 227-234 (opinion of Gray, J.).
Footnote 31
The authority of the view that Parliament's sovereignty must be indivisible had already
been eroded in the decade before independence. Iredell himself, as early as 1774,
rejected the applicability of the theory "to the case of several distinct and independent
legislatures each engaged within a separate scale and employed about different objects,"
in the course of arguing for the possibility of a kind of proto-federalist relationship
between the Colonies and the King. Iredell, Address to the Inhabitants of Great Britain,
in 1 G. McRee, Life and Correspondence of James Iredell 205, 219 (1857, reprinted
1949); see Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution, at 224-225,
and n. 64.
Footnote 32
This is entirely consistent with, and indeed is a corollary of, the statement quoted
by the Court that the States are " `no more subject, within their respective spheres,
to the general authority than the general authority is subject to them, within its
own sphere.' " Ante , at 4 (quoting The Federalist No. 39, p. 245 (J. Madison)). The
point is that matters subject to federal law are within the federal sphere, and so
the States are subject to the general authority where such matters are concerned.
Footnote 33
It is therefore sheer circularity for the Court to talk of the "anomaly," ante ,
at 43, that would arise if a State could be sued on federal law in its own courts,
when it may not be sued under federal law in federal court, Seminole Tribe , supra
. The short and sufficient answer is that the anomaly is the Court's own creation:
the Eleventh Amendment was never intended to bar federal-question suits against the
States in federal court. The anomaly is that Seminole Tribe , an opinion purportedly
grounded in the Eleventh Amendment, should now be used as a lever to argue for state
sovereign immunity in state courts, to which the Eleventh Amendment by its terms does
not apply.
Footnote 34
Perhaps as a corollary to its view of sovereign immunity as to some degree indefeasible
because "fundamental," the Court frets that the "power to press a State's own courts
into federal service to coerce the other branches of the State ... is the power first
to turn the State against itself and ultimately to commandeer the entire political
machinery of the State against its will and at the behest of individuals." Ante ,
at 40. But this is to forget that the doctrine of separation of powers prevails in
our Republic. When the state judiciary enforces federal law against state officials,
as the Supremacy Clause requires it to do, it is not turning against the State's executive
any more than we turn against the Federal Executive when we apply federal law to the
United States: it is simply upholding the rule of law. There is no "commandeering"
of the State's resources where the State is asked to do no more than enforce federal
law.
Footnote 35
Furthermore, the very idea of dignity ought also to imply that the State should be
subject to, and not outside of, the law. It is surely ironic that one of the loci
classici of Roman law regarding the imperial prerogative begins with (and is known
by) the assertion that it is appropriate to the Emperor's dignity that he acknowledge
(or, on some readings, at least claim) that he is bound by the laws. See Digna Vox,
Justinian's Code 1.4.14 (" Digna vox maiestate regnantis legis alligatum se principem
profiteri ") ("It is a statement worthy of the majesty of the ruler for the Prince
to profess himself bound by the laws"); see Pennington, The Prince and the Law, 1200-1600,
at 78, and n. 6.
Footnote 36
The Court also claims that subjecting States to suit puts power in the hands of state
courts that the State may wish to assign to its legislature, thus assigning the state
judiciary a role "foreign to its experience but beyond its competence . . . ." Ante
, at 43. This comes perilously close to legitimizing political defiance of valid federal
law.
Footnote 37
In its discussion of Hilton , the Court attempts to explain away the State's failure
to raise a sovereign immunity defense by acknowledging candidly that when that case
was decided, "it may have appeared to the State that Congress' power to abrogate its
immunity from suit in any court was not limited by the Constitution at all." Ante
, at 27. The reasoning of Hilton suggests that it appeared not only to the State,
but also to the Court, that Congress could abrogate state sovereign immunity in state
court. If Congress could not, then there would have been no jurisdiction in the case.
The Court never even hinted that constitutional structure, much less the Tenth Amendment,
might bar the suit, even though the dissent stressed that "the principle of federalism
underlying the [Eleventh] Amendment pervades the constitutional structure," 502 U.
S., at 209 (opinion of O'Connor , J.).
Footnote 38
Nor does Poindexter v. Greenhow, 114 U. S. 270 (1885), one of the Virginia Coupon
Cases, fit comfortably with the assumption that state courts have exercised no disputed
jurisdiction over their own governments on federal questions. Under its Funding Act
of 1871, Virginia had issued bonds that specified on their face that the attached
coupons should be receivable at and after maturity for all taxes, debts, dues, and
demands due the State. Id ., at 278. In 1882, however, Virginia passed a law requiring
its tax collectors to accept nothing but gold, silver, or currency in payment of taxes.
Id ., at 275. After the bonds reached maturity, Poindexter used them to pay state
property taxes; Greenhow, the local tax collector, ignored the payment and took possession
of an office desk in Poindexter's possession to sell it for unpaid taxes. Poindexter
brought a common-law action in detinue against the tax collector in state court for
recovery of the desk, arguing that the later Virginia statute barring use of the coupons
violated the Contracts Clause. Greenhow defended, inter alia , on the theory that
the suit was "substantially an action against the State of Virginia, to which it has
not assented." Id ., at 285. The Court rejected this claim by applying to the State
of Virginia reasoning akin to, though broader than, that later adopted in Ex parte
Young, 209 U. S. 123 (1908). We held that, where state legislative action is unconstitutional,
it "is not the word or deed of the State, but is the mere wrong and trespass of those
individual persons who falsely speak and act in its name," 114 U. S., at 290 . Because
the original bonds were binding contracts, the obligation of which Virginia could
not constitutionally impair, "[t]he true and real Commonwealth which contracted the
obligation is incapable in law of doing anything in derogation of it." Id ., at 293.
It therefore could not be argued that the tax collector was acting on behalf of the
State, because "[t]he State of Virginia has done none of these things with which this
defence charges her. The defendant in error is not her officer, her agent, or her
representative, in the matter complained of, for he has acted not only without her
authority, but contrary to her express commands." Ibid . Although the tax collector
had done nothing more than collect taxes under duly enacted state law, he was held
to be liable to suit. Thus in the only case to have come before this Court specifically
involving a claim of state sovereign immunity of constitutional magnitude in a State's
own court, jurisdiction was upheld.
Footnote 39
Garcia demonstrates that, contra the Court's suggestion, the FLSA does not impermissibly
act upon the States, see ante , at 4. Rather, the FLSA, enacted lawfully pursuant
to the commerce power, treats the States like other employers. The Court seems to
have misunderstood Hamilton's statement in The Federalist No. 15 that the citizens
are " `the only proper objects of government,' " ante , at 4 (quoting Printz v. United
States, 521 U. S. 898, 919-920 (1997)). Hamilton's point is not, as the Court seems
to think, that the National Government should dictate nothing to the States in order
to protect their residual sovereignty. To the contrary, Hamilton, who was arguing
against the extreme respect for state sovereignty in the Articles of Confederation,
meant precisely that the National Government should not act as the leader of a "league,"
The Federalist No. 15, p. 95 (J. Cooke ed. 1961), mediating among several sovereignties,
but as a "national government," ibid ., with power to produce obedience through the
"COERCION of the magistracy," ibid . Hamilton is therefore the wrong person to quote
for the proposition that the National Government may not act upon the States, since
his point was that the National Government should not be limited to acting through
the medium of the States.
Footnote 40
The most recent available data give 4,732,608 as the total number of employees of
the 50 States of the Union, see State Government Employment Data: March 1997, http:/www.census.gov/pub/govs/apes/
97stus.txt.
Footnote 41
The principle is even older with respect to rights created by statute, like the FLSA
rights here, than it is for common-law damages. Lord Holt in fact argued that the
well-established principle in the context of statutory rights applied to common law
rights as well. See Ashby v. White , 6 Mod., at 54, 87 Eng. Rep., at 816 ("Now if
this be so in case of an Act of Parliament, why shall not common law be so too? For
sure the common law is as forcible as any Act of Parliament"). A still older formulation
of the statutory right appears in a note in Coke's Reports: "[W]hen any thing is prohibited
by an Act, although that the Act doth not give an action, yet action lieth upon it."
12 Co. Rep. 100. Coke's Institutes yield a similar statement: "When any act doth prohibit
any wrong or vexation, though no action be particularly named in the act, yet the
party grieved shall have an action grounded upon this statute." 1 E. Coke, The Second
Part of the Institutes of the Laws of England 117 (1797) (reprinted in 5B 2d Historical
Writngs in Law and Jurisprudence (1986)). In our case, of course, the statute expressly
gives an action.
Footnote 42
See, e.g. , A Declaration of Rights and Fundamental Rules of the Delaware State §12
(1776), 2 Sources and Documents of United States Constitutions, at 197, 198; Md. Const.
Art. XVII (1776), 4 id ., at 372, 373; Mass. Const. Art. XI, (1780), 5 id ., at 92,
94; Ky. Const. Art. XII, cl. 13 (1792), 4 id ., at 142, 150; Tenn. Const. Art. XI,
§17 (1796), 9 id ., at 141, 148.
Footnote 43
Unfortunately, and despite the Court's professed "unwilling[ness] to assume the States
will refuse to honor the Constitution and obey the binding laws of the United States,"
ante , at 46, that presumption of the sovereign's good-faith intention to follow the
laws has managed somehow to disappear in the intervening two centuries, despite the
general trend toward greater, not lesser, government accountability. Anyone inclined
toward economic theories of history may look at the development of sovereign immunity
doctrine in this country and see that it has been driven by the great and recurrent
question of state debt, both in the aftermath of Chisholm and in the last quarter
of the 19th century, see Seminole Tribe , 517 U. S., at 120 -122 ( Souter , J., dissenting).
And no matter what one may think of the quality of the legal doctrine that the problem
of state debt has helped to produce, one can at least argue that States' periodic
attempts to repudiate their debts were not purely or egregiously lawless, because
those who held state-issued bonds may well have valued and purchased them with the
knowledge that default was a real possibility.
Maine's refusal to follow federal law in the case before us, however, is of a different
order. Far from defaulting on debt to eyes-open creditors, Maine is simply withholding
damages from private citizens to whom they appear to be due. Before Seminole Tribe
was decided, petitioners here were the beneficiaries of a District Court ruling to
the effect that they were entitled to some coverage, and hence to some amount of damages,
under the FLSA. Mills v. Maine , 839 F. Supp. 3 (Me. 1993). Before us, Maine has not
claimed that petitioners are not covered by the FLSA, but only that it is protected
from suit. Indeed, Maine acknowledges that it may be sued by the United States in
federal court for damages on the very same claim, Brief for Respondent 12-13, and
we are told that Maine now pays employees like petitioners overtime as covered by
the FLSA, id ., at 3. Why the State of Maine has not rendered this case unnecessary
by paying damages to petitioners under the FLSA of its own free will remains unclear
to me. The Court says that "it is conceded by all that the State has altered its conduct
so that its compliance with federal law cannot now be questioned." Ante , at 50. But
the ambiguous qualifier "now" allows the Court to avoid the fact that whatever its
forward-looking compliance, the State still has not paid damages to petitioners; had
it done so, the case before us would be moot.